The Project Gutenberg eBook of Gambling; or, Fortuna, her temple and shrine.

This ebook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this ebook or online at www.gutenberg.org . If you are not located in the United States, you will have to check the laws of the country where you are located before using this eBook.

Title : Gambling; or, Fortuna, her temple and shrine.

Author : James Harold Romain

Release date : July 29, 2019 [eBook #60005]

Language : English

Credits : Produced by Turgut Dincer, Charlie Howard, and the Online
Distributed Proofreading Team at http://www.pgdp.net (This
file was produced from images generously made available
by The Internet Archive)

*** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK GAMBLING; OR, FORTUNA, HER TEMPLE AND SHRINE. ***

  

Gambling:
Or, Fortuna, her Temple and
Shrine. The True Philosophy
and Ethics of Gambling. By
James Harold Romain.

CHICAGO:
The Craig Press.
1891


COPYRIGHT, 1891.

JAMES HAROLD ROMAIN.


3

Publisher’s Note to the Public.

America is free and her people boast of her freedom in every realm of thought and every department of activity. Her pride is a form of discussion from which no man is excluded because of the opinions he may advocate. We declare a man should be heard in the very face of prejudice or passion.

Mr. Romain’s book, in our judgment, is entitled to publication for other reasons than those above mentioned. It is replete with learning, and original in conception. The philosophy is broad and the tone dignified. Patient research is manifest in every page. Every branch of knowledge has been made to contribute its force to the argument. The work is a mine of information in political speculation, social science and moral philosophy. Mr. Romain is obviously in sympathy with the widest possible circle of culture. For that reason, if for no other, what he has to say is entitled to a respectful consideration. His book is unique in design and wrought out with vigor. His appeal is to philosophy, science and history; not to idle curiosity, purposeless gossip, or the unimportant “personal equation” to which others have been so prone.

In the interest of fair play, but, confessedly, with no sympathy for gambling, the book is offered to the people to decide as to the correctness of its conclusions.

Adam Craig , Publisher.


5

This book is dedicated
To the
Hon. John Cameron Simonds,
by the author,
as a token of esteem for his
fair-mindedness and sense of justice.
Although that gentleman is not a gamester,
nor in sympathy with the pursuit,
yet the author desires thus to acknowledge his
indebtedness to him for many valuable suggestions
in the preparation of this work.


7

PREFACE.

Two doughty knights, clad cap-a-pie in burnished mail, once journeyed forth in search of martial adventure. Their noble steeds all caparisoned for war, both wandered up and down through the world, defending the fair and protecting the weak. Betimes they chance to meet where stood in majestic beauty a bronze statue of victory. In her right hand the goddess clasped a sword, while in graceful pose her left rested upon an ægis richly wrought in the precious metals. Approaching from opposite directions, to one warrior the shield appeared as of gold, while to the other it was of silver. 8 Low were bowed their crested helms in courtly salutations.

“Comely, Sir Knight,” said one, “comely and noble is this figure.”

“Yea, thou hast spoken truly,” was the reply.

“Precious, very precious,” rejoined the first, “must be yon golden targe.”

“Nay, Sir Knight, it is of silver, I trow.”

“By my lady, thou liest,” quickly came the hot retort.

Then, prancing chargers well in hand, with lances lowered to deadly level, they prepared for the “wager of battle.” Both were unhorsed in the onslaught. Regaining an upright posture, with swords drawn to renew the duel, each observed that his reverse of the shield was what the other had contended for. Moral: It is wise to look first upon both sides of the subject.

Not so, it is evident, has it been with books heretofore devoted to a discussion of gambling. Their authors professed an exposition 9 of gaming in the interest of morality. Well may some of the books be read for their wealth of information and excellent diction. Some have been earnest, in places eloquent, and often suggestive. Vivid and dramatic are the descriptions of a passion that has possessed the world in all ages; yet, that the various assaults were conceived in wisdom, or that they have resulted in permanent good, I am constrained to deny.

True, I believe with Sir Walter Raleigh, that out of history may be gathered a policy no less wise than eternal; “by the comparison and application of other men’s forepassed miseries with our own like errors and ill-deservings.”

But why did it not occur to these writers that circumstances should not be recorded merely because they have happened; that events deserve memorial only because they illustrate some great principle; because some inference is to be drawn from them, which may increase the happiness or enlarge 10 the powers of man? That it did not, we must infer from the pages they have given to the world. Cicero declared that “History is the light of truth.” In vain, however, do we look for a consideration of causes in any history of gambling. “Histories,” said Carlyle, “are as perfect as the historian is wise.” Is that book wise wherein no adequate remedy is suggested for the evil it depicts? Although interesting, such a work is but a chronicle devoid of moral purpose. It is clear, to dwell upon the follies of man will not cure them; that it will not strengthen humanity merely to portray their weaknesses. The passion our author would combat is rooted in the soul.

“Whose powers at once combat ye, and control,
Whose magic bondage each lost slave enjoys.”

How would you extirpate the evil, if such it is? Expose a folly, you may say, and wisdom will turn from it. You would have us believe, perhaps, that:

“Wisdom from heaven received her birth;
Her beams transmitted to the subject Earth.”

11 And yet

“This great empress of the human soul
Does only with imagined power control,
If restless passion, by rebellious sway,
Compels the weak usurper to obey.”

So far as the history of gambling has ignored causes and neglected remedies, it is incomplete. That it is deficient in both is my reason for this book. Some one should begin the subject where other authors have deserted it.

I have long made a study of gaming in all its aspects and relations; aiming, the while, at breadth, impartiality and thoroughness. At first my reading was not conducted with a view to authorship. I desired information for its own sake. As a gamester, I sought the philosophy of gaming.

What is chance? How far does it influence all mankind and circumscribe their efforts? What is gambling, in the broadest sense of the term? Is gaming wrong per se : i.e., absolutely vicious? Where in human 12 nature is the passion grounded? Why does the propensity exist? Is it an inevitable tendency of human nature? What is morality? Wherein does the gambler differ from other men? How should his occupation be distinguished from business generally? How far may the conduct of an individual be dictated by society? How may the essentially punitive be distinguished from that which is not so? What are the true limits of State power in relation to appetites and propensities? Are sumptuary laws effectual? Does history, as the philosophy of example, justify such enactments? Can the law eradicate innate tendencies? Can character be transformed by statute? Is it possible to legislate morality into mankind? What should be the policy of statesmen and reformers in the realm of morals? If it is not possible to extirpate the passions by law, how may they be regulated, directed, educated and purified?

Such were the problems that confronted 13 my understanding. Each and all were resolved to the best of my knowledge and capacity. I make my observations public in the interests of fair play and common sense. I am at least entitled to the literary chances of a reading age.

I have dallied with fickle fortune for years. As gamester, I anticipated prejudices against the pursuit. My deductions are amply fortified, therefore, from the mature studies of great and wise men. I did not expect my book to stand unsupported. It is substantiated, throughout, by the teachings of profound and impartial philosophers.


17

CONTENTS.

Page
Publisher’s Note , 3
Dedication , 5
Preface , 7
Introduction , 19
The Worship of Fortuna , 27
What is Truth; or, The Philosopher’s Stone? 46
The Destinies; or, The Reign of Law , 103
Legislative Exorcism; or, The Belief in Word-Magic , 139
“The King is Dead—Long Live the King!” , 211

19

Introduction.

INTRODUCTION.

A traveler once sought to explore an unknown country. Compass he had not, and both chart and guide were wanting. In the distance a mountain loomed above the plain. To its summit our traveler made his way. From thence he beheld the region stretching away in all directions. The land he would traverse the eye could now sweep from center to circumference. It was not possible to know the landscape in detail, but the relative proportions, distances and boundaries were unfolded at his feet. So, when properly conceived, with the introduction to a book. A perspective of the topic is conducive to a better understanding of its scope and purpose. My object is to sustain the following propositions:

22 First. —Men have gambled in all ages of the world. That they will continue to do so is a reasonable presumption. To gamble would seem instinctive—inherent in the souls of mankind and fostered by the very nature of their environment. History reveals that all alike are possessed by this subtle passion—male and female, young and old, good and bad, wise and unwise, rich and poor, the exalted and the lowly. In every century may be seen a motley throng kneeling in devotion at the feet of Fortuna. Eagerly about her shrine press the mighty concourse of emperors, kings, chieftains, statesmen, ecclesiastics, savants, philosophers, poets, soldiers and the wayfaring. Now and ever will mankind court the mysterious and uncertain.

Second. —To define a wager is to defy intolerance of opinion. Truth is not absolute but relative. It is not to be established ex cathedra . Moralists are not in a position to denounce gambling per se . They are not yet agreed upon the unconditioned principles of 23 right and wrong. Before it can speak with authority, moral philosophy must find an ultimate, self-evident and irrefragable foundation. That it is essentially criminal or necessarily vicious to invoke a chance has never been demonstrated. To live is to gamble. We all wager in one way or another. Luck is appealed to in every department of human activity. Everywhere uncertainty is the rule and certainty the exception. In the business world vast realms are specifically founded upon the doctrine of chances. If absolutely wrong, then gambling should be discountenanced in all persons under every circumstance. In whatever guise it should be condemned as a principle. Until this has been done society is not in a position to punish in one person what it permits or commends in another. In its treatment of gambling the law is now inconsistent, unjust and hypocritical.

Third. —Man is the creature of circumstances. Society is an organism conditioned by its environments. Every nation must complete 24 a cycle of infancy, youth, manhood and old age. Briefly, history is a science—an unbroken chain of causes and effects throughout the ages. Volition, so-called, is delusive and shadowy—more apparent than real. At best, we but yield to the greatest pressure of temperament or motive. Human nature, in a word, is the result of inevitable tendencies. The passions are inherent and cannot be violently uprooted. Character is innate and not subject to arbitrary reform by extrinsic force. Here, as elsewhere, evolution is the law of existence. While our appetites and propensities may be educated, they can never be obliterated. Social and political philosophy have repeatedly deduced these truths from the history of man. In the field of reform officialism has been repudiated by the greatest thinkers. Legislation, therefore, should conform to the light of experience and the dictates of science. Ergo : in the future, as in the past and present, the gaming passion will everywhere assert itself, 25 despite repressive legislation, however severe.

Fourth. —Sumptuary statutes are futile and impertinent. They are to-day and ever have been indefensible and impolitic. Such laws are an infringement upon individual rights and an insult to human nature. Officious and pharisaical legislation in the province of morals and taste should be abandoned once and forever. Per se , to gamble is neither a sin nor a crime. For the law to punish the practice is futile and unwarranted.

Conclusion. —An enlightened age demands the overthrow of an effete administrative policy. In the realm of morals, let that be wisely guided which the law cannot prevent. Gambling, with certain conditions, should be licensed and placed under the surveillance of a police.


27

The Worship of Fortuna.

CHAPTER I.
The Worship of Fortuna.

Reader, in imagination go backward with me more than 20 centuries. Enter with me the magnificent and imposing Temple of Fortuna, in old Præneste. We are within the portico of that stately hemicycle. Far above is the marble dome, and about us cluster the snowy columns. As it is early morn, flamens and virgins are assembled inside the sacred precincts. They are grouped about the flaming tripod, and the robes of purple and white blend in harmony of color. The sanctuary is redolent with burning incense. A golden image of the goddess, in heroic mould, flashes back the rays of sunlight that penetrate the inner shadows. A solemn 30 chant entrances the ear, and our eyes turn to the westward. Before us expands the Campagna, ninety miles in length and twenty-seven in breadth. The undulating plain stretches away in all directions until it sinks into the sea; thickly studded is the superb picture with prosperous cities and “every rood of ground maintains its man.” Everywhere is presented an appearance of comfort and rich cultivation. Yonder, Mount Albanus towers to a height of 3,000 feet above the sea. Looming majestically above its topmost peak is the Temple of Jupiter Latiaris. The grandeur of mighty Rome is at our feet, a splendid and stupendous panorama of temples, amphitheatres, basilicas, palaces, circuses, baths, arches and aqueducts. Such was the spot dedicated to Fortuna by the ancient Prænestians. She was more deeply enshrined in their hearts than Olympian Jove himself.

Præneste flourished before the birth of Christ or the glory of Rome. The noble city occupied a projecting point or spur of 31 the Apennines and was distant from Rome, due east, about twenty-three miles. Above its walls towered the Temple of Fortuna. The Temple proper was circular in form and crowned the summit of a hill more than 2,400 feet above the Mediterranean level. Standing out boldly against the sky, its majestic outlines were visible from a great part of Latium. As extended by Sulla, the sanctuary occupied a series of six vast terraces, which, resting on gigantic substructions of masonry, and connected with each other by grand staircases, rose one above the other on the hill, in the form of a pyramid. Closely associated with the ritual of the Temple were the “Prænestine Lots,” or Sortes Prænestinæ, and in existence at the beginning of the Christian era. Constantine, and subsequently Theodosius, suppressed the oracle. Its celebrity is attested by Lucan, Horace and Ovid. Cicero speaks of the great antiquity and magnificence of this shrine. Numerous were the great men 32 who petitioned the Prænestine Fortuna for assistance. Of the number may be mentioned Tiberius, Domitian and Alexander Severus. Even Sulla sought to propitiate the goddess before engaging in his successful wars with Mithridates.

Plutarch tells us of Timotheus, the Athenian, son of Conon, who, “when his adversaries ascribed his successes to his good luck, and had a painting made representing him asleep, and Fortune by his side, casting her nets over the cities, was rough and violent in his indignation at those who did it, as if, by attributing all to Fortune, they had robbed him of his just honors; and said to the people, on one occasion, at his return from war: ‘In this, ye men of Athens, Fortune had no part!’ A piece of petulance which the deity played back upon Timotheus; who, from that time, was never able to achieve anything that was great.”

“Sylla,” he continues, “on the contrary, not only accepted the credit of such divine 33 favors with pleasure, but gave the honor of all to Fortune. He once remarked: ‘that of all his well-advised actions, none proved so lucky in the execution, as what he had boldly enterprised, not by calculation, but upon the moment.’ He gave Fortune a higher place than merit, and made himself ‘entirely the creature of a superior power.’”

The Goddess of Chance, or Good Luck, actually existed in the imagination of the ancients. Chapman writes:

“The old Scythians
Painted blind Fortune’s powerful hands with wings,
To show, her gifts come swiftly and suddenly,
Which, if her favorites be not swift to take,
He loses them forever.”

Temples to Fortuna (the Greek Tyche) dotted the sunlit landscape from Thebes to Rome. She was adored by the Etrurians as Nortia. Originating near Mount Parnassus, her worship gradually extended into all parts of Greece and Italy. Antium, an opulent and powerful city of Latium, was once celebrated for its splendid temple of Fortune.

34 History discloses not a period, however remote, when Fortuna was not a favorite with the Latins. Numa Pompilius daily prostrated himself before her altar, and the ceremonial received a new impetus from his pious grandson, Ancus Martius. Servius Tullius ascribed his power and success to the gods. Especially did he assume the protection of Fortuna. Two temples were erected to her by this great king, one in the Forum Boarium and the other on the Tiber. By some it is said that the edifices were respectively dedicated to Bona Fortuna and Fors Fortuna. Yet another gorgeous structure afterward graced the Quirinal.

Precisely when the mythological system lost its influence is not known. It is not true, however, as was once generally believed, that immediately after the birth of Jesus the oracles were forever hushed. While, long prior to that event, many fanes had been deserted, yet others continued to flourish for at least two centuries thereafter. Before 35 the Christian era, Mythology had been repudiated by Philosophy and Science. To the learned it was at best but expressive of the principles back of natural phenomena. Only because it was largely identified with the state, did it receive the support of politicians. Yielding to the spirit of Christianity, the Olympian deities departed with the decline of Rome as a pagan power.

Of all the shining throng that beautified the Pantheon, Fortuna alone refused to abdicate a sovereignty she would exercise to the end of time. True, the exquisite forms in which she had charmed the eye were destroyed and her temples razed with the earth; yet has Fortuna continued her uninterrupted sway over the hearts of men. Sanctuaries and statutes were not necessary to her supremacy in the world. She was enshrined in the soul—her worship instinctive in the very nature of humanity. Where is the epoch of Christendom in which an innumerable multitude have not worshiped this 36 imperial goddess? Among her devotees may be included men famous in every department of life: politics, statesmanship, war, eloquence, philosophy, science, art, literature and the liberal professions. A review of the brilliant procession is profoundly suggestive.

Great Cyrus, who founded the Persian monarchy; Darius, who originated centralized imperialism and reduced it to a system; Artaxerxes Third, the greatest administrator of remote antiquity; Miltiades, a name associated with the glories of Marathon, once designated “freedom’s best and bravest friend;” Themistocles, to whom may be fairly ascribed the victory at Salamis; Simonides, gentle and patient, the poet of nationality and patriotism; Aristophanes, the great father, and Menander, the acknowledged master of Greek comedy; Pericles, the “Olympian Zeus of oratory,” a great statesman and one of the most remarkable characters of Greece; Plato, whose name 37 is synonymous with all that is most exalted in idealism; Xenophon, a friend and pupil of Socrates, and to whom the world is indebted for “Memorabilia,” “Anabasis,” and “Cyropædia;” Demosthenes, known to oratory as the “greatest Hellenic star;” Isocrates, his contemporary, the distinguished rhetorician; Philip of Macedon, the famous father of a more famous son; great Alexander, “Child of Zeus,” “Son of Peleus,” familiar to every schoolboy as the greatest of military conquerors.

In the resplendent story of Rome are Scipio Africanus, a military genius, and the conqueror of Hannibal; Cornelius Sulla, the great general, sagacious politician, accomplished scholar, “one of the most remarkable figures of all time;” Julius Cæsar, equally preëminent in statecraft, war and letters; Marc Antony, brave and generous; Lepidus, not the least of the second great triumvirate; Augustus, than whom a more consummate ruler and prudent statesman never lived; 38 Tiberius, a writer of Greek odes and an orator at nine years of age; in battle he repeatedly worsted the Parthians, Cantabrians, Dalmatians, Pannonians and Illyrians; Domitian, conspicuous for his piety, who enforced the laws against adultery and other gross forms of immorality; Titus, bewailed at his death as “the love and light of the human race;” Hadrian, just, liberal, valorous and energetic; Nerva, humane and progressive; Trajan, indomitable and heroic; Alexander Severus, a virtuous prince, a student of Christianity, and the friend of Paulus and Ulpian; Sallust, distinguished in Latin literature for power and animation; Livy, the man of beautiful genius; the graceful Catullus; exquisite Horace and facile Ovid.

Among the Germanic peoples, Eugene of Savoy, a memory cherished by Austria, who lived but for glory, and raised the Hapsburg arms to a prestige unequaled before or since; Wallenstein, bold, imperious and of versatile ability in civil and military affairs.

39 In Italy, the Abbes Ruccellai and Frangipanni, pious and charitable; Reni Guido, who painted the marvellous “Crucifixion of St. Peter’s,” and the “Aurora.” In art, he expressed a most refined and fervent spiritualism.

The Fifth, Sixth and Seventh Charles of France, distinguished, respectively, as “The Wise,” “The Beloved,” and “The Victorious;” Charles VIII., who, with but 9,000 soldiers, defeated an Italian army of 40,000 men; Louis XI., ever admirable for his administrative talent, a friend of the middle classes, he restrained a turbulent and oppressive nobility; Louis XII., of France, a “father of the people;” Louis XIII., distinguished for valor and martial ability; Louis XIV., better known to the world as “The Great,” and to his country as Dieu-donne—“God-given;” the amiable and picturesque Henry of Navarre, the champion of Protestantism and protector of the Huguenots; Philibert de Chalon, fertile and resolute; 40 Bertrand du Guesclin, “king of the tournament,” the “hero of heroes;” Condé and Turenne, both profound and alert; Marshall Saxe, energetic and courageous; Napoleon Bonaparte, a titanic genius of transcendent powers, king of kings, “the astonishment and terror of the world;” Ney, bravest of the brave, the victor of Elchingen, Mannheim and Moskva; Murat, “the Gold Eagle,” a truly wise king, and the greatest cavalry leader of his time; Richelieu, greatest statesman of the 17th century; Mazarin, brilliant in ministerial policy, and the wise architect of peace at Westphalia; Mirabeau, a man of gigantic thoughts and deeds—the mental Colossus of his age—“an intellectual Hercules;” Talleyrand, unexcelled in diplomacy and eminent as a financier; Thiers, equally able in politics and literature; M. Sallo, counselor to the Parliament of Paris, and Mathieu Mole, at one time the Premier-President of that body; Molière, the inimitable; Corneille, creator of French tragedy; Rotrou, 41 his master; and Racine; Montaigne, the essayist, extraordinary for his learning and sound reason; Paschasius Justus, an erudite and excellent physician; Rousseau, apostle of universal happiness, and unrivaled in the literature of France for the subtle eloquence of his style; Voltaire, world-famous Sage of Ferney, the “sovereign writer of his century;” René Descarte, deservedly exalted in philosophy and mathematics; the delightful poets, Voiture and Coquillart, with the renowned Cardinals D’Este and De Medicis.

Fair Albion comes into the story with “Lion-Hearted” Richard, the incomparable knight-errant; Edward I., unequaled in his century as warrior and ruler; Edward III., who befriended literature and art, and espoused the cause of progress; his son, the Black Prince, “most glorious star of chivalry;” Henry VIII., a foe to papacy, and for a time the most popular monarch in English history; “Ye Merrie King Charles;” Duke of Marlborough, the brilliant and successful general; 42 Arthur Wellesley, “The Iron Duke,” venerated and beloved; Horatio Nelson, of magnificent exploits and stupendous victories, who said: “Where anything great is to be done, there Providence is sure to direct my steps;” unrivaled was he in daring resource and skill; Sir Charles Napier, conqueror of Sinde and the “acknowledged hero of a family of heroes;” Dan Chaucer, “that first sweet warbler” of English verse, philosopher, politician and poet; Marlowe, the mightiest of Shakespeare’s pioneers; Shakespeare, himself, “sweet swan of Avon,” myriad-minded and wondrous; “rare” Ben Jonson; Raleigh, a universal genius—“the glass of fashion and mould of form;” Surrey, polished and chivalric; John Dryden, of whom Dr. Johnson said: “As Augustus was to Rome, so was Dryden to English literature. He found it brick and left it marble;” Dr. Tobias Smollett, who wrote “Humphrey Clinker;” Fielding, the frank and manly author of “Tom Jones;” sweet Oliver Goldsmith, 43 in letters perspicuous, vivacious, and graceful; Halifax,

“Jotham of piercing wit and pregnant truth,
Endued by nature and by learning taught
To move assemblies;”

the first Marquis of Anglesey, high-spirited and impetuous, a dashing general of cavalry; that best of Irish Viceroys, Frederic Howard, Earl of Carlisle; Lord Bolingbroke, accomplished and eloquent; Shaftesbury, the incorruptible statesman, upright judge and friend of religious freedom; Horace Walpole, of whom Macaulay said, that his writings “were among the delicacies of intellectual epicures;” Dr. Dodd, divine, author, editor and chaplain of the king; George Selwin, the celebrated conversational wit; Sir Philip Francis, immortal as “Junius,” and a “friend of the people;” the artistic Farquhar; courtly Waller; elegant Dorset; charming Sedley; and scholarly Congreve; jolly Dick Steele, a master of classical prose; Charles James Fox, of whom James Mackintosh said: “He is 44 the most Demosthenian speaker since Demosthenes;” Sheridan, “capable of the grandest triumphs in oratory,” and noted for his sparkling wit and exquisite songs; Wilberforce, who dedicated his life to a struggle for the abolition of the slave-trade; Edward Gibbon, the historian, splendid, imposing and luminous; Ponsonby, once speaker of the Irish House of Commons; Dr. Colton, author of “Lacon;” William Pitt, of dauntless spirit and unimpeachable integrity; and Lord Byron, a poet famed for his passionate eloquence and pathetic gloom.

Fortuna may proudly enumerate her great votaries in America: Aaron Burr, Edgar Allan Poe, William Wirt, Luther Martin, Gouverneur Morris, Daniel Webster, Henry Clay, General Hayne, Sam Houston, Andrew Jackson, Generals Burnett, Sickles, Kearney, Steedman, Hooker, Hurlbut, Sheridan, Kilpatrick, Ulysses S. Grant, George D. Prentiss, Sargeant S. Prentiss, Albert Pike, A. P. Hill, Beauregard, Early; Ben Hill, Robert Toombs, 45 George H. Pendleton, Thaddeus Stevens, Green of Missouri, Herbert and Fitch of California, “Jerry” McKibben, James A. Bayard—father of the recent Secretary of State—Benjamin F. Wade, the lamented Broderick, John C. Fremont, Judge Magowan, Charles Spencer, Fernando Wood and his brother Benjamin, Colonel McClure, Senator Wolcott, Senator Pettigrew, Senator Farwell, Matthew Carpenter, Thomas Scott, Cornelius Vanderbilt, Hutchinson of Chicago, and Pierre Lorrillard. Names might be extended indefinitely. Enough have been mentioned to illustrate how the gambling habit permeates all ranks of society in the United States.

With the conclusion of our retrospect, we may well exclaim: What is the nature of a passion so inveterate and general: of a propensity that dominates all mankind alike, whether noble or mean, wise or foolish, strong or weak? “Is there a remedy?” propounds the philosopher. The legislator asks, “What is my duty?”


46

What is Truth?
or,
The Philosopher’s Stone.

49

CHAPTER II.
What is Truth; or, the Philosopher’s Stone?

In mediæval romance the Alchemist is a familiar figure—with flowing robe and skull-cap, in the midst of crucibles and alembics. This period of the world did not present a feature more weird and picturesque: a body of learned but misguided men, professing the “chemistry of chemistries.” With eagerness and devotion they vainly sought for a principle that could indefinitely prolong human life and transmute the baser metals into gold and silver. Although centuries have elapsed since Gebir and Paracelsus, yet the “philosopher’s stone” is a desideratum. Of the Alchemists it has been quaintly said by Percy, “that their respective histories were 50 accurate illustrations of the definition which describes Alchemy as an Art without principle, which begins in falsehood, proceeds in labor, and ends in beggary.”

Forcibly suggestive is this picture of moral philosophy and philosophers. From the remotest ages certain men have arrogated to themselves a knowledge in the realm of ethics much superior to their brethren. It was manifested by the “gnomic” poetry of Greece, more than 700 years B. C., and in the oracular sayings of the so-called “seven sages” of antiquity. To this day a similar class of wiseacres may be found in all parts of the earth. The moralists, however, search not for the universal medicine or an irresistible solvent. Such persons admit the “grand elixir” is a delusion; and yet, their ambition is more daring and presumptious. They would “be as gods, knowing good and evil.” “Gold is but dross,” they exclaim, “our quest is for necessary moral truth. We seek immutable righteousness.” Long ago was Alchemy 51 abandoned as futile. Not so the egotistic dogmatism of the moral philosophers: with them self-conceit has remained incorrigible, from Socrates and Plato, through Kant and Hegel, to Martineau and Janet. In vain, their assumptions have been repeatedly demolished and their deductions refuted. Unmindful are they, also, of the irreconcilable conflict of “schools”—the hopeless contradiction of “systems.” Fully one hundred great thinkers, first and last, have asserted the discovery of indubitable “good.” But no two of them all agreed upon the infallible line of distinction between what “ought to be” and its opposite. In fact, every individual of the number represents a different scheme. All moral philosophers asseverate the necessity for an authoritative standard of right and wrong—for some peremptory and incontestable guide to human conduct. Otherwise, they admit, one opinion is no more acceptable or commanding than another.

52 Some affirm the existence of an innate faculty, the unerring dictates of which are defended. But Bentham (a great jurist) denounced the “moral sense” man as a bully who would brow-beat others into accepting his verdict. All such appeals were described by him as sheer “ ipse dixitism : as a fraud by which incompetent philosophers would palm their own tastes and fancies upon mankind.” “One man,” wrote Bentham of Shaftesbury, “says he has a thing made on purpose to tell him what is right and what is wrong; and that it is called moral sense : then he goes to work at his ease and says such and such a thing is right, and such and such a thing is wrong. Why? ‘Because my moral sense tells me it is.’” Of the inner-capacity-philosopher, Hazlitt remarked that “his excessive egotism filled all objects with himself.” To Crabbe, “he was a self-conceited man, who pretends to see through intuition what others learn by experience and observation; to know in a day what another wants 53 years to acquire; to learn of himself what others are contented to get by means of instruction.”

Archdeacon Paley, again, ridiculed as worthless a “moral sense” which man may disregard if he chooses. What is an authority , said Paley, merely felt in the individual consciousness: a personal whim, the mere accident of individuality. What, he asks, is the authority of another’s conscience to me? What, indeed, is my conscience, and why is it an authority to myself? We can never know whether it is “a real angel with flaming sword, or a scare-crow dressed up by the moral philosophers.” Did the “moral sense” exist, should we not see a universal evidence of its influence? Would not men exhibit a more manifest obedience to its supposed dictates than they do? Would there not be a greater uniformity of opinion, as to the rightness or wrongness of opinions, as to the rightness or wrongness of actions? “We should, not, as now, find one man or nation 54 considering as a virtue what another regards as a vice—Malays glorying in the piracy abhorred by civilized races—a Thug regarding as a religious act that assassination at which a European shudders—a Russian piquing himself on his successful trickery—a red Indian in his undying revenge—things which with us would hardly be boasted of.

“Again, if this moral sense exist and possess no fixity, gives no uniform response, says one thing in Europe and another in Asia—originates different notions of duty in each age, each race, each individual, how can it afford a safe foundation for a systematic morality? What can be more absurd than to seek a definite rule of right in the answers of so uncertain an authority?”

Can it be fairly said, my reader, that such men are in a position to judge the gambler, or to denounce his vocation? May not the gamester ask of this sect: By what authority do you pronounce judgment, “out of hand,” upon me and mine? Where is your standard—authentic, 55 determinative, undeniable, irrefutable? Am I subject to the dominion of your conscience? In my opinion, gaming is not a sin. In what is your judgment superior to mine? Moreover, I defy you to demonstrate a wager is wrong, per se . If you find this impossible, I am free to repudiate your dogmatism. To know, also, that gaming is not prima facie sinful, we have but to define it.

The lexicographers define a gamester as “one who plays for money or other stake;” and gaming “to be the use of cards, dice, or other implement, with a view to win money, or other thing, wagered upon the issue of the contest.” Is this a description of anything forbidden by the decalogue? Where, in the old or new testament, is a similar transaction denounced as a sin? But, it may be said, perhaps, the foregoing definition does not suffice for moral consideration: it ignores the element of chance, which enters more or less into all games. 56 This would imply that it is immoral to invoke a fortuity. Is it?

Here, the great Jefferson may be quoted with propriety: “It is a common idea that games of chance are immoral. But what is chance? Nothing happens in this world without a cause. If we know the cause, we do not call it chance, but if we do not know it, we say it was produced by chance. If we see a loaded die turn its lightest side up, we know the cause, and that it is not an effect produced by chance; but whatever side an unloaded die turns up, not knowing the cause, we say it is the effect of chance. Yet, the morality of the thing cannot depend on our knowledge or ignorance of its cause. Not knowing why a particular side of an unloaded die turns up, cannot make the act of throwing, or of betting on it, immoral. If we consider games of chance immoral, then every pursuit of human industry is immoral, for there is not a single one that is not subject to chance; not one, wherein you 57 do not risk a loss for the chance of some gain.”

In “Paradise Lost,” Milton declares:

“Next him, high arbiter,
Chance governs all!”

And of mankind we read in Ecclesiastes that “time and chance happeneth to them”—mankind. (9:11). Among the Hebrews, property was divided and disputes were decided, “by lot.” The custom is mentioned by Solomon, Matthew and Luke. (Prov. 16:33; Matt. 27:35; Luke 10.) Furthermore, this mode of appeal to destiny is sanctioned, yea, even prescribed, by the Bible. According to Leviticus, Aaron was commanded “to take the two goats, and present them before the Lord, at the door of the tabernacle of the congregation. And Aaron shall cast lots upon the two goats; one lot for the Lord and the other lot for the scape-goat. And Aaron shall bring the goat upon which the Lord’s lot fell, and offer him for a sin offering. But the goat on which the lot fell to be the 58 scape-goat, shall be presented alive before the Lord, to make an atonement with him and to let him go for a scape-goat into the wilderness.” (16:7, 8, 9.)

Thus was chance invested with the sanctity of a religious observance.

Moses was instructed that the “Promised Land” should be divided among the Hebrews “by lot.” The method is described in Numbers: “Notwithstanding, the land shall be divided by lot, according to the names of the tribes of their fathers shall they inherit. According to lot shall the possession thereof be divided between many and few.” This direction was followed to the letter by “Eleazar, the priest, and Joshua the son of Nun, and the heads of the fathers of the tribes of the children of Israel;” for we are told in Joshua, that “By lot was their inheritance; as the Lord commanded by the hand of Moses, for the nine tribes and for the half tribe.” (Josh 14:1, 2; 18:6.)

Luck, then, decided the tenure of the 59 tribes in Canaan—a title dictated by Divinity.

Joshua determined, by lot, that it was Achan, of the tribe of Judah, who had taken “the accursed thing” and thus brought upon Israel the disaster at Ai. (Josh. 7:14.) During the great battle of Michmash-Aijalon, Saul said unto the Israelites: “Cursed be the man that eateth any food until evening, that I may be avenged on my enemies.”

Unmindful of this oath, wild honey was eaten by his son, in a moment of extreme hunger. No one would divulge that the king’s adjuration had been disregarded by the beloved Jonathan. “Therefore, Saul said unto the Lord God of Israel, give a perfect lot. And Saul and Jonathan were taken: but the people escaped. And Saul said, Cast lots between me and Jonathan, my son. And Jonathan was taken.” (1 Sam. 14:40, 42.)

By lot, likewise, the question of “ministry 60 and apostleship” was decided against Justus and in favor of Matthias. (Acts 1:26.)

Briefly, if the Bible is a divine production, how can appeals to chance be stigmatized as vicious or irreligious? Also, it is not to be denied that chance, or casualty, enters very largely into every department of human action. Men are compelled to take ventures every day; the engineer faces them; so does the sea captain; the same may be said of the doctor, the surgeon, the lawyer and the banker. A merchant encounters all the risks of trade; the hostility of the elements and the bankruptcy of others. The rains may rot or the drouths destroy the crops of the farmer. And almost, in the words of Ben Jonson, throughout the world,

“All human business, fortune doth command,
Without all order, and with her blind hand,
She, blind, bestows blind gifts, that still have nurst,
They see not who nor how.”

The politician, too, might say with Macbeth: “If chance will have me king, why, chance may crown me.” War is a mighty game 61 between giants. In truth, of Napoleon the poet has said:

“Whose game was empires, and whose stakes were thrones,
Whose table, earth; whose dice, were human bones.”

Beyond this, even our laws and institutions appeal to chance. In the United States Senate, whom, respectively, of two members—elected at the same time—shall serve for the long and short term, is decided by lot. The law recognizes that even property may be thus divided. “When an estate is apportioned into three parts, and one part is given to each of three persons; the proper way is to ascertain each one’s part by drawing lots.” Thus is the rule stated by Bouvier and Wolff. The Illinois Statutes, for the regulation of elections, enact that “when two or more persons receive an equal and the highest number of votes for an office to be filled by the county alone, that county clerk shall issue a notice to such persons of such tie vote, and require them to appear at his office, on a day named in the notice, 62 within ten days from the day of election, and determine by lot which of them is to be declared elected. On the day appointed the clerk and other canvassers shall attend, and the parties interested shall appear and determine by lot which of them is to be declared elected.” Similar laws exist in other states.

Some moralists admit the validity of a transaction, notwithstanding it may depend upon chance. They will concede there is no intrinsic wrong in any species of game, unless there exists an inequality of chance or skill. Not so, thought Paley, the Christian philosopher, whose name is a household word for purity, zeal and power. He said: “What some say of this kind of contract, that one side ought not to have any advantage over the other, is neither practical nor true. This would require perfect equality of skill and judgment, which is seldom to be met with. I might not have it in my power to play with fairness a game of cards once in 63 a twelvemonth, if I must wait till I meet with a person whose art, skill and judgment are neither greater nor less than my own. Nor is this equality requisite to the justice of the contract. One man may give to another the whole of the stake if he chooses, and the other may justly accept it if it be given him; much more, therefore, may one give another an advantage in the chance of winning the whole. The only proper restriction is, that neither side have an advantage by means of which the other is not aware. The same distinction holds of all transactions and proceedings into which chance enters; such as insurance, and speculations in trade or in stocks.”

In this connection, with what force could be quoted the sweet Nazarene in His parable of the vineyard laborers: “Friend, I do thee no wrong; didst thou not agree with me for a penny? Take that thine is, and go thy way; I will give unto this last even as unto thee. Is it not lawful for me 64 to do what I will with mine own? ” (Matt. 20:13, 14, 15.)

Here the mathematicians attempt to rescue moral philosophy. They would demonstrate the improbability of luck. If asked how it happened that a man won a hundred thousand dollar prize, while his neighbor drew a blank, the mathematician might tell you it was chance; that there was a necessity for the prize to fall somewhere, and that he who had the most chances was the most likely to obtain it. Such caviling could be dismissed with the answer: You acknowledge the necessity of a prize falling somewhere , then why not to me. Surely my chances are as good as my neighbors’, perhaps more so. It may be; and what may be may be now. “There is no prerogative in human hours.” “There is a tide in the affairs of men, which taken at the flood, leads on to fortune.”

No intelligent gambler is a believer in “luck” as a personal quality . He recognizes the phenomena of chance. How they will 65 operate is not known to the mathematician more than to him; the “chances” may result favorably or unfavorably for a gambler; the law may so work as to benefit him, or it may not. Whether “chance” or “luck,” is immaterial to the issue.

But seriously, for what do these aspirants contend? A method of reasoning from the happening of an event to the probabilities of one or another cause; that the possible combinations in a pack of cards, or a handful of dice, may be computed, even when the question involves the chances of a thousand dice, or a thousand throws of one die. In its very nature this is a vain-glorious pretension, and upon what is it based? An hypothesis presenting the necessity of one or another out of a certain number of consequences. In other words, given an event as having happened, and which might have been the consequence of either of several causes, or explicable by either of several hypotheses , the probabilities can be inferred .

66 In this way is the philosophy of supposition substituted for that of caprice. We are asked by the mathematician, at the very outset, to assume something he has not proved, and which is not susceptible of proof. We are required to take for granted the imaginary premises upon which his argument depends. Is this not the acme of intellectual audacity? But having yielded his antecedent proposition, what is the result? A bare probability—a mere likelihood of the occurrence of any event.

So much for the boasted “Doctrine of Chances.” Besides, I assert that every premise of the mathematician has been refuted by my experience as a gamester. In the proper place, I could disprove his every theory with a fact. For example: De Morgan and Proctor tell us that it is not probable seven could be thrown ten successive times, with a pair of dice. We are told, on good authority, that in 1813, a Mr. Ogden wagered 1,000 guineas that his opponent 67 would not perform this feat. That gentleman threw seven nine times running.

However, the mathematicians are not concerned with the right or wrong of play for money. They seek to demonstrate the inequalities of chance, hoping thus to dissuade humanity from its pursuit. Their efforts are idle. “The proverb which advises us to throw a sprat to catch a whale, shows that mankind consider a chance of a gain to be a benefit for which it is worth while to give up a proportionate certainty.” These gentlemen have extended their conjectures to the risks of loss or gain in general commerce; the probable continuity of life and duration of marriage; the contingencies in political results and the verdicts of juries; the distributions of sex in births, and even the probability of error in any opinion that may be generally received. In fact, should their guesses be heeded by the world, enterprise and hope would depart.

Another class of moralizers reject and 68 deride the idea of “innate notions.” Truth, they maintain, is not to be found in worn out abstractions and moral senses, which are the weak reproductions of material organisms. In ethics, if they are to be followed, we must set out with the convictions that our materials are relative and not absolute, and that our highest moral conceptions must partake of the same character. As stated by Posnett, systems of ethics, more or less perfect in their day, have vanished in the progress of society and mind. Systems of ethics, whether we see or care to see it, are gliding from amongst us at this moment, while others, “with strange faces are growing familiar by the slowness of their approach.”

To illustrate from Chenebix: Nothing can appear more definite than virtue; yet, in Asia, the term may denote submission; in Europe and America, resistance; to Mussulmans war; to Christians, peace. Honor, too, which its votaries describe as one and incorruptible, assumes various significations. 69 In some countries it prescribes revenge for an injury received; in others, forgiveness. Here, the violation of female chastity is a disgrace, elsewhere it is a duty. To a Mussulman the eating of pork is “vile and unclean: fills his soul with aversion, repugnance, disgust. To this habit their antipathy is deep and intuitive. To the natives of Western India, eating beef is sacrilegious and revolting. In Spain, any other worship than that established by the Catholic church is impious and in the highest degree offensive to God. The people of all Southern Europe regard a married clergy as irreligious, indecent, unchaste, gross and disgusting. Wherever the Puritans have been sufficiently powerful they have endeavored to put down all public, and nearly all private amusements: music, dancing, the theatre and public games.”

This denomination, strange as it may seem, also urge upon mankind what, in their opinion, is the “true moral rule”—the correct standard of right. It is that which is established 70 by authority, custom, or general consent. A variable and doubtful criterion, this, one would naturally suppose. How severely has it been treated by Spencer and Carpenter. Right and wrong are not essentially different. All moral distinctions are a matter of arbitrary establishment by the “powers that be.” That which is statutory, customary, fashionable, or generally habitual, is fit and proper. Conduct is purely a question of majority and might. Place gambling in the ascendant to-morrow and it would be just; or, as the major part of humanity, gamesters would be respectable; for an opinion commonly accepted is the correct opinion. With this as a guide, can the state hold the gamester reprobate?

Society keeps changing its sentiments with the centuries. Absolutely, we can never know when it is right or when it is wrong. The outlaw of one era is the idol of another. Servetus was immolated by the Calvinists, to-day he is a martyr to conscience. Bruno 71 was burned as a heretic, now he is the hero of philosophy and science.

Galileo and Roger Bacon were once execrated by the church—their bones lie in unknown and unhonored graves. We regard them as brave pioneers of human thought. The formerly despised and hunted Christians are become the greatest power on earth. The Jew money-lender of the “dark ages” (whom such as Front-de-Bœuf once tortured with impunity) is the Rothschild of our century—“the guest of princes and the instigator of commercial wars.” Shylock is now an influential and courted capitalist. “All the glories of Alexander do not condone, in our eyes, for his cruelty in crucifying the brave defenders of Tyre, by thousands, along the sea-shore; and if Solomon, with his thousand wives and concubines, were to appear in London or New York to-morrow, even the most frivolous circles would be shocked, and Brigham Young, by contrast, seem a domestic model.”

72 From Cæsar we learn that the Suevi held their lands in common; that private property in the soil did not obtain with the Gauls and Germans. The same is true of the North American Indians and some of the Pacific Islanders. It is conceded, moreover, that communistic principles were generally prevalent in the earliest ages of the world. Then, any attempt at exclusive individual possession of land or chattel would have been deemed a theft.

The mediæval ideal was an ascetic and monastic life. To-day, millions regard such a course as unwise, if not wicked. Poverty, heretofore esteemed as the badge of honor and dignity, is by our era adjudged offensive. Nomadism prevailed in a former age. Now gypsies and tramps are the outcasts of society. Regarding marriage, public opinion has varied through all phases, without attaining finality. In earliest times how indiscriminate is the tie—the monstrous relation of brother and sister being the rule, rather than the exception. 73 Polygamy prevails with one people and polyandry among another. In India and the Orient a wife is hidden from the dearest friend, while in Africa a chief will put his mate to bed with a guest. In Japan young women, even of good birth, “are free in their intercourse with men, till they are married; at Paris they are free after.”

In ancient Greece and Rome, again, marriage was not the highest conception, and largely “a matter of convenience and housekeeping.” Wives were little, if any better, than slaves. The class of women known as Hetairai (concubines and mistresses) were openly honored and trusted by both political and social leaders. The name of Aspasia is closely associated with that of Pericles. Theodota was the intimate of Socrates. Diotima has been immortalized in the “Symposium” of Plato.

The splendid ideal of our century is the monogamic state—“the great theme of romantic literature, and the climax of a 74 myriad novels and poems.” In classic Greece the idealistic model was male friendship—comradeship. We have its type in the heroic figures of Harmodius and Aristogiton. The Theban Legion, or “Sacred Band,” exemplified the principle. No man might enter without his lover. Although annihilated at the battle of Chæronæa, it was never vanquished. The literature of Greece and Rome illuminate this exalted sentiment. The writings of Pliny the younger, Cicero and Lucian, are worthy of especial mention. Many sweet and noble friendships are embalmed in the poetry of Hellas and Latium; Demetrius and Antiphilus; Damon and Pythias; Phocion and Nicoles; Glaucus and Diomedes; Philades and Orestes; Cicero and Atticus; Socrates and Alcibiades; Lucilius and Brutus; Tiberius Gracchus and Blossius; Caius Gracchus and Licinus.

Suicide was not thought unworthy by the ancients. It was resorted to by Anthony, Brutus, Cassius, Cato, and Zeno. To-day, 75 the attempt is a crime, and its consummation a disgrace. In Europe and America it is felo-de-se . Infanticide is common in many parts of Asia and Africa. To-day the feudal baron would be adjudged a freebooter; the knight-errant a brawling vagabond. A nineteenth century man may beat his wife within an inch of her life, and get but three months. For stealing a suit of clothes he would be “sent up” for years. So “gambling on ’change is now respectable enough, but pitch and toss for halfpence is low, and must be dealt with by the police. We know that when questions connected with life contingencies were first considered, it was regarded as most deliberate gambling to be in any way concerned in buying or selling such articles as annuities, or any interests depending upon them.” The age boasts of an advance in the humanities; and yet, public opinion permits extravagance and selfishness in the rich while the poor are starving. Our educated classes, generally, approve the vivisection 76 of animals. In ancient Egypt it would have been stigmatized as the most abominable of crimes.

From age to age, likewise, law represents the code of the dominant or ruling class—at all times only valid because it is the code of those in power. How often used by “authority” for selfish purposes, may be read on every page of history. Monarchy, absolute or limited, is a synonym for injustice. Feudalism is another term for murder, rapine and extortion. In Spain, the lands of nobles were long exempted from direct taxation. For centuries the Hungarian turnpikes were free to the aristocracy. Prior to the revolution in France, all burdens of state devolved upon the lower classes. Less than two centuries ago Scotch lairds exported their peasantry into slavery. Students will recall the “Black Act” of George I., and the “Inclosure Laws” of England. Until quite recently, slavery existed in Europe and America; nor has the institution wholly disappeared 77 from the earth. Legislation is mainly in the interest of the wealthy and powerful. Congress and legislatures are making the rich richer, and the poor poorer. Government is largely devoted to the creation and upholding of corporations, trusts, monopolies, subsidies and extortionate tariffs. What care the politicians for manhood? Wealth is their God.

“Let your rule be the greatest happiness to the greatest number,” interposes another authority. But are men agreed in their definition of “greatest happiness?” Different notions of it are entertained in all ages, amongst every people, by each class. “To the wandering gypsy a home is tiresome, whilst a Swiss is miserable without one. Progress is necessary to the Anglo-Saxons; on the other hand, the Esquimaux are content in their squalid poverty, have no latent wants, and are still what they were in the days of Tacitus. An Irishman delights in a row, a Chinaman in ceremonies and pageantry, 78 and the usually apathetic Javanese gets vociferously enthusiastic over a cock-fight. The heaven of the Hebrew is a city of gold and precious stones, with an abundance of corn and wine; that of the Turk, a harem peopled by Houris; that of the American Indian, a happy hunting-ground; in the Norse paradise there were to be daily battles, with magical healing of wounds. It was, seemingly, the opinion of Lycurgus, that perfect physical development was the chief essential to human felicity; Plotinus, on the contrary, was so purely ideal in his aspirations as to be ashamed of his body. To a miserly Elwes, the hoarding of money was the only enjoyment of life; but the philanthropic Day could find no pleasurable employment, save in its distribution.”

Francis, Duke of La Rochefoucault, likened the soul of man unto a medal, so constructed that it may represent either a saint or a devil. Montaigne, also, said the soul of man was double-faced; the inner 79 beamed upon self-love, while the outer wore a mask. Voltaire was a scoffer: a master of satire, who ridiculed without mercy every human weakness. In “Zadig” and “Micromegas” he mocked the ignorance and self-conceit of mankind. His “Memnon,” the “Wise Memnon,” who, in the morning, foreswore all women, made a vow of temperance, renounced gaming and quarreling, and determined never to be seen at court, was, before the night of the same day, cheated and robbed by a female, got drunk, gamed, quarreled with his most intimate friend, and made a visit to court, where everyone laughed at him. The moral of “Candide, or the Optimist,” is, as interpreted by Smollett, that nothing is more absurd than the exercise of human reason; that nothing is more futile and frivolous than the cultivation of philosophy; that mankind are savages, who devour one another. This is cynicism, pure and simple. I cannot endure a creed so ghastly: a philosophy that suspects Socrates 80 of incontinence, charges Epicurus with prodigality, accuses Aristotle of covetousness, and can say of Seneca that “he had but the single virtue of concealing his vices.” Horace took a more charitable view of the moral philosophers, and ascribed their weakness to inability rather than hypocrisy. The poet says that men “upon the stage of this world are like a company of travelers whom night has surprised as they are passing through a forest; they walk on, relying upon the guide, who immediately misleads them through ignorance. All of them use what care they can to find the beaten path again; everyone takes a different path, and is in good hopes his is the best; the more they fill themselves with these vain imaginations the farther they wander; but though they wander a different way, yet it proceeds from one and the same cause; ’tis the guide that misled them, and the obscurity of the night hinders them from recovering the right road.”

In truth, the mind of man, unaided by 81 Divine light, is not able to determine what is absolutely right or absolutely wrong. In the realm of morals, man is to be guided only by the decrees of God, if known. For those who recognize the Bible as His word, the way is clear. Aside from this, the path is dark and uncertain. But nowhere in either the Old or New Testament, is gambling forbidden. Not a word did Moses or Jesus utter against it, as a general principle, or in any of its particular forms. What is commanded by God is our only test of right and wrong. Theology is of man, and yet it is a fact that gambling, in itself, is not inconsistent with the profession of any creed in Christendom. The ablest theologian cannot successfully challenge this proposition.

For the sake of argument, heretofore, I have granted the moral freedom of man. The fact is, I deny his “liberty,” save in the most restricted sense. I am convinced every action is determined by the resultant force of conflicting motives. However, the possible 82 autonomy of man is not necessary to a consideration of what it is right or best to do. It is only when we ask about the conduct of man, in his relation to the law, that it is important to know whether he could have done otherwise. I reserve the topic for a subsequent chapter.

Be this as it may, certain conclusions are obvious to the impartial observer. It is very difficult, if not impossible, to draw a strict boundary between the virtues and vices. Courage should not be carried to the point of rashness. Timidity is the abuse of prudence. Generosity can degenerate into improvidence. Reverence might merge into credulity and superstition. Arrogance is the extreme of self-respect. Chastity is overdone by the monastic. Some writers, in fact, deny a fixed line between the virtuous and vicious passions; this class boldly maintain a place for both vices and virtues. Hatred may be just and anger magnificent. Although out of place in a drawing-room, obstinacy is 83 a virtue on the field of battle. Love is divine and lust monstrous. Are they not yoke-fellows? Reformers, so called, are impossible without stupid candor and impassive bluntness. Timidity, on the other hand, is the defect of a sensitive temperament. Sensuality underlies the domain of art, painting, sculpture and music.

This is suggested by Plato in the “Phædrus”—an allegory of the soul, wherein the spirit of man is depicted as a chariot to which are attached a white and black horse. The first typifies our higher and the latter our lower passions.

Mr. Lecky writes in his “History of Morals,” that in society certain defects necessarily accompany certain excellencies of character. He remarks, “Had the Irish peasants been less chaste they would have been more prosperous.” “Habitual liars and habitual cheats have been industrious, amiable and prudent.” “Civilization is not favorable to self-sacrifice, reverence, enthusiasm or 84 chastity.” He declares of the gambling table, “that it fosters a moral nerve and calmness scarcely exhibited in equal perfection in any other sphere—a fact which Bret Harte has finely illustrated in his character of Mr. John Oakhurst, in the ‘Outcasts of Poker Flat.’”

This thought is boldly illustrated by Mandeville, in his “Fable of the Bees:”

“These were called knaves, but, bar the name,
The grave industrious were the same:
All trades and places knew some cheat,
No calling was without deceit.
The root of evil, avarice,
That damn’d, ill-natured, baneful vice,
Was slave to prodigality,
That noble sin ; whilst luxury
Employed a million of the poor,
And odious pride a million more:
Envy, itself, and vanity
Were ministers of industry,
Their darling folly, fickleness,
In diet, furniture and dress,
That strange, ridiculous vice, was made
The very wheel that turned the trade.”

The author of this unique production 85 announced that his main design was to indicate the impossibility of enjoying all the most elegant comforts of life “that are to be met with in an industrious, wealthy and powerful nation, and at the same time be blessed with all the virtue and innocence that can be wished for in a golden age; from thence to expose the folly and unreasonableness of those that, desirous of being an opulent and flourishing people, are wonderfully greedy after all the benefits they can receive as such, are yet always murmuring against those vices and inconveniences, that from the beginning of the world to the present day, have been inseparable from all the kingdoms and states that ever were formed for strength, riches and politeness.”

“To do this, I first slightly touch upon some of the faults and corruptions the several professions and callings are generally charged with. After that I show that those very vices of every particular person, by skillful management, were made subservient to the 86 grandeur and worldly happiness of the whole. Lastly, by setting forth what of necessity must be the consequence of general honesty, virtue, innocence, content and temperance, I demonstrate that if mankind could be cured of the failings they are naturally guilty of, they would cease to be capable of being raised into such vast, potent, and polite societies, as they have been under the several commonwealths and monarchies that have flourished since creation.”

Not yet, then, have we found the human standard by which the gambler is to be denounced.

Gamblers are accused of avarice, and an inordinate desire for wealth. As a rule, the gamester is not penurious. A miserly or covetous grasp of money is inconsistent with his vocation. Concede the accusation, and is he alone? Is he more greedy of gain than other men? History refutes the charge. Money is the god of the world. Get enormous wealth is the cry, no matter 87 how; no matter how many impoverished widows and squalid orphans are crying out to heaven, day and night, against you; and such slavish adulation as the world knows not beside are yours. The passion for wealth increases gradually, as its end is achieved, the world over. Its effects are manifest wherever men strive for gold.

“Gold! gold! gold! gold!
Bright and yellow, hard and cold,
Molten, graven, hammered, rolled;
Heavy to get, and light to hold;
Hoarded, bartered, bought and sold;
Stolen, borrowed, squandered, doled;
Spurned by the young, but hugged by the old
To the very verge of the church-yard mould,
Price of many a crime untold;
Gold! gold! gold! gold!”— Thomas Hood.

The morale of gambling is not to be determined by political economy, which is not a part of moral philosophy. It is not founded on the imperations of duty, but upon the adequate footing of desirableness of self-interest. In the language of Prof. Perry: “One word circumscribes the 88 field of morals, ought. One word defines the field of economy, expediency.” So far as it is a science, political economy is cold and selfish; “budded on monopoly values.” Judged by such a standard, gambling would be right, if expedient.

Yes, but is not gambling a destructive luxury? Is it not a wasteful expenditure of money? I answer, what is luxury, and is it always an evil? Roscher well says: “The idea conveyed by the word is an essentially relative one.” Every individual calls all expenditure with which he chooses to dispense, a luxury. The same is true of every age and nation. “’Tis a word without any specific idea,” wrote Voltaire, “much such another expression as when we say Eastern and Western hemispheres: in fact, there is no such thing as East and West; there is no fixed point where the earth rises and sets; or, if you will, every point on it is, at the same time, East and West. It is the same with regard to luxury; for 89 either there is no such thing, or else it is in all places alike.... Do we understand by luxury the expense of an opulent person? Must he, then, live like the poor, he whose profusion, alone, is sufficient to maintain the poor? Expensiveness should be the thermometer of a private person’s fortune, as general luxury is the infallible mark of a powerful and flourishing empire.... Money is made for circulation. He who hoards it is a bad citizen, and even a bad economist. It is by dissipating it we render ourselves useful to our country and ourselves.” David Hume also thought the word of uncertain signification. He said: “The bound between virtue and vice cannot here be exactly fixed, more than in other moral subjects. To imagine that the gratification of any sense, or the indulging of any delicacy, is of itself a vice, can never enter into a head that is not disordered by the frenzies of enthusiasm. These indulgences are only vices, 90 when they are pursued at the expense of some virtue, as liberality of charity; in like manner as they are follies, when a man ruins his fortune and reduces himself to want and beggary.” Again, William Roscher, the political economist, was of opinion that “prodigality is less odious than avarice; less irreconcilable with certain virtues;” and that “prodigality, directly or indirectly, increases the demand for commodities.” We know the Epicureans and Stoics were reproached with being bad citizens, because their moderation was a hindrance to trade. Gambling is no more a luxury than many other practices of mankind. Some persons may prefer it as a pastime to any other form of luxury. Who is to decide a question of taste and expense but the individual concerned? One man indulges lavishly in pictures, books, and clothes; another is prodigal in the matter of tobacco and liquors; a third delights in the excitement of chance. All 91 these inclinations are luxurious. Which is preferable to each, is not for society to determine in one case, more than in the others. In a word, the phases of luxury are so variable and extensive that it is equally unjust and impracticable for the state to discriminate unfavorably.

The gambler is said to be idle and non-productive: that a quid pro quo is not given for what he receives. What is meant here by idleness and non-production? Does it signify that labor is the proper basis of exchangeable value: the only just source of what is called wealth? If so, the condemnation includes all who obtain wealth without working for it. Suppose it be admitted that service is the one equitable title to property. What, then, of assumed rights, in the form of profits, dividends, rent and interest? If true wealth is the outcome of physical labor, are not banker, broker, middleman, landlord, capitalist, gentleman of leisure and gambler on the same footing.

92 Bishop Jewel once said: “If I lend £100, and for it covenant to receive £105, or any other sum greater than was the sum I did lend, this is that we call usury: such a kind of bargaining as no good man, or godly man, ever used.” Many contend that interest contributes nothing to the support of society, but is a tax on labor. Those who receive it are said to be extortioners who live on the gains of other people. Christ, Buddha, Zoroaster, and Mahomet all put usury in the category of forbidden sins.

It is discountenanced by Ezekiel, Moses, David, Aristotle, Cato, St. Basil, Masse, Bacon, Buxton, Dr. Wilson and Fenton. Ricardo, the great economist, was of the opinion that rent is not a creation of wealth, and adds nothing to the necessaries, conveniences and enjoyments of society. Adam Smith, the father of political economy, considered rent as a monopoly price paid for the use of land. Were this true, the owner of a house, when it had paid for itself, could 93 rightfully charge for its use, the cost of his labor in transferring it to you, and the amount of wear and tear.

It is said of the gambler that he is not a man of equivalents. But, if wealth is to be a question of exact equality in values and labor, then must business generally be condemned. The great legists, Pomponius and Paulus, unblushingly said, that “In buying and selling, a man has a natural right to purchase for a small price what is really more valuable, and to sell at a high price what is less valuable, and for each to overreach the other.” Harsh as this may seem, it but voiced the principles of trade in every age of the world. “Trade is war,” said the ancient proverb; “and as a nail between the stone joints, so does sin stick fast between buying and selling.” Business is advantage-taking erected into a system. Get as much more than you give as is possible. A thing is worth what it will bring. You may rightfully take from another what 94 he is compelled to yield. Exchange is not a rendering of equivalent for equivalent; but an effort to get the largest possible amount of another’s property, or services, for the least possible return. In business, justice and mercy are daily displaced by extortion and mastership: “the producing classes are vassal to the speculating classes; the creators of wealth to its stealthy possessors.”

The Christian Fathers deprecated trade. “To seek to enrich one’s self is in itself unjust,” said Clement; “since it aims at appropriating an unfair share of what was intended for the common use of men.” “If covetousness is removed,” argued Tertullian, “there is no reason for gain, and, if there is no reason for gain, there is no need of trade.” Jerome taught that “as the trader did not himself add to the value of his wares, therefore, if he gained more for them than he paid, his gain must be another’s loss.” To Augustine, “business in itself is 95 an evil, for it turns men from seeking true rest, which is God.” Aquinas decided “that to buy a thing for less, or sell a thing for more than its value is, in itself, unallowable and unjust.”

It has been estimated by Bastiat, Karl Marx and Nordau, that laborers are unjustly deprived of the value of four days labor in each week. Terrible is the injustice to wage-earners, the world over, if the deductions of Carpenter and Godwin are to be accepted. “Behold the hire of the laborers which is of you kept back by fraud, crieth: and the cries of them are entered into the ears of the Lord of Sabaoth.” Proudhon and Spencer have revealed the “economic’s lies” of modern society. “The great game of the business world is the game of getting on,” wrote John Ruskin; “not of everybodies getting on, but of somebody getting on. What to one family is the game of getting on, to one thousand families is the game of not getting on. Nay, 96 you say, they have all their chance. Yes, so has every one in a lottery, but there must always be the same number of blanks. Ah! but in a lottery it is not skill and intelligence that take the lead, but blind chance. What then! do you think the old practice that they should take who have the power, and they should keep who can, is less iniquitous when the power has become the power of brains instead of fist?”

Is this a world of equivalents in labor? What is the ratio of riches awarded to those who toil? In 1860, the net average income was but three per cent. Yet, for that year the income of bare money (which needs no food, clothing or shelter), was all the way from five to thirty per cent. In England 30,000,000 people are taxed that interest may be paid to 300,000. In 1870, the interest on the national debts of the world amounted to $1,700,000,000. This rate in nine years would absorb a sum equal to the entire property of this country in 1870. We are 97 informed that trade is annually taxed (interest on capital) about $200,000,000, for which not one dollar of actual service is rendered. Is interest on “watered” stock any better than theft?

A world of equivalents, indeed! In our cities five per cent of the population own more property than ninety-five per cent; and twenty per cent of the nation own more than the remaining eighty per cent. At the present rate of increase, within thirty years, 100,000 persons will own four-fifths of all the property in the United States. In twenty-five years the number of our people who own their homes has decreased from five-eighths to three-eighths. In New York City more than 1,100,000 persons are dwelling in tenement houses. “In 1889, the farm mortgages in the western states amounted to three billion four hundred and twenty-two million dollars .” In England, to-day, there are less than 30,000 landed proprietors—one-half of the country 98 is owned by 150 men. Twelve men own one-half of Scotland. The working classes of the United Kingdom own but a thirtieth part of the total real and personal property.

Strictly considered, two things are said to be equivalent when they are “equal in value.” Generally speaking, however, interchanges are seldom, if ever, “alike in worth.” The equality of labor for labor does not occur once in millions of times. “Value” is an indefinite term. Into “worth” enters such intangible qualities as whim, caprice, taste, fancy, ambition, pride, habit, desire, appetite, passion and amusement. Exact and utilitarian standards would destroy belle lettres and the fine arts; dissipate recreation and the amenities of life. Are there precise “work-a-day” equivalents for literature, music, sculpture, painting; for the opera, the theatre, the salon, the club-room? Gaming is an amusement for many persons. Thousands enjoy the excitements of chance. It stimulates their spirits above the cares and 99 drudgery of existence. Such men prefer a game to either book, piano or cigar. With them it is not a question of utility but of diversion. Is the value of entertainment to be measured in muscle or metal?

Wherein, essentially, does gaming differ from speculation or insurance? All have their foundation in chance. Contingencies and uncertainties enter into each as a consideration for investment. A gamester bets upon the turn of a card, or the cast of a die. The speculator purchases in anticipation of contingent advance in the price of a commodity. A corporation indemnifies an individual, conditionally, against possible death or loss by fire. In neither instance can the result be foretold: the gamester may or may not win, the speculator may or may not realize a profit, the assured may or may not forfeit his life policy, or lose by fire. In every transaction, fortuity is the controlling element; if for 100 this reason any one is invalid or immoral, so are the others. Large sums have been won and lost at cards. Many fortunes had their origin in speculation: also, it has been productive of widespread disaster, distress and despair. Insurance companies have benefited thousands of widows and orphans. Innumerable are the families upon whom indigence has fallen through the forfeiture of policies. Forfeited premiums to the amount of millions are now invested in palatial structures throughout the civilized world. Analysis might show in gaming, speculation and insurance, that at least the equities and ethics are even.

View the subject as we may, ye gamester, “where is thine accuser?” To all men he can say: “He that is without sin among you, let him first cast a stone.”

Now, some one may ask: “Is not gambling immoral to the extent it may induce a reliance upon chance for a livelihood, instead of patient industry.” I might reply: “What 101 is industry, as known to political economy; and what proportion of the world’s wealth is a result of direct personal exertion?” But, generally, men are rational creatures, and do not depend upon games of chance for a living. The credulous men are relatively few who rely entirely upon the outcome of chance in games as a business; and those few are at least on a par in wisdom and ethics with the millions who gamble in future prices of stocks, grain, and other commodities. “Ah! but you forget,” rejoins my critic, “that in other pursuits a man produces something by his industry, or contributes to that result indirectly, whereas in gambling nothing is produced.” I consider this erroneous, in the face of social experience, as has been indicated heretofore. It may be as soundly said, that a “man has no right to invest his money in cattle, or lands, or bonds, unless his labor is put in with it. A man buys a horse and hires him to his neighbor. 102 Is he entitled to the money his horse earns for him? He invests in bonds at fifty cents on the dollar. Does he not hope they will appreciate in value, until they are worth dollar for dollar? He pays $1000 for a piece of land. In two or three years, perhaps, his neighbors have invested around him, and have improved their properties, and he finds that his land will sell for $2000. His labor did not contribute to that result. He risked his capital exactly as he would have done in a game of chance.”


103

The Destinies;
or,
The Reign of Law.

105

CHAPTER III.
The Destinies; or, The Reign of Law.

On one occasion, an aged scholar soliloquized as follows: “Homer was at the same time beggar and poet: his mouth more often filled with verses than with bread. Plautus turned a mill that he might live. Menander, Cratinus and Terrence were drowned; Empedocles lost in the crater of Mount Etna; Euripides and Heraclitus torn to pieces by dogs; Hesiod, Archilochus and Ibychus, murdered. Sappho threw herself from a precipice. Condemned by a tyrant, respectively, Seneca, Lucan, and Petronius Arbiter, cut their veins and bled to death. Poison terminated the lives of Socrates, Demosthenes and Lucretius.

106 “In Plutarch, we read of ‘two eminent persons, whose names were Attis, the one a Syrian, the other of Arcadia, both were slain by a wild boar; of two, whose names were Acteon, one was torn to pieces by his dog, the other by assassins; of two famous Scipios, one overthrew the Carthagenians in war, the other totally destroyed them; four of the most warlike commanders of antiquity had but one eye—Philip, Antigonous, Hannibal and Sertorius.’

“Paul Borghese, a writer of rhythmic verse, died of starvation. Tasso, himself the most amiable of poets, lived like a pauper, and passed away in an asylum. Bentivoglio, a creator of classic comedies, in the misery of his old age, was refused admittance to an hospital he had founded. Cervantes died of hunger, and Camoens ended his days in an almshouse. The body of Vaugelas was disposed of to surgeons that his debts might be paid. Spencer was forsaken and neglected in his old age. Decker, 107 Cotten, Savage and Lloyd breathed their last in jails.

“Might not these men have said, ‘Who can shut out fate?’ Were they the sport of circumstances, or could circumstances have been made their sport? Was each independent of fatality? Was he free from destiny; or, was he subject to an unalterable course—an invincible necessity?”

The query of this venerable sage has been that of civilized man in every age. Coming into the world with the dawn of philosophy, it will remain until the veil of Isis is uplifted. Profoundest wisdom has ever taught the subordination of man to a higher law, by which his career is largely determined from the beginning. Investigation will disclose that such, to-day, is the real opinion of a vast majority of mankind.

The thought was ascendant in the literature and religion of the ancient Greeks. Their Moira was a personification of law; the Goddess of Destiny, who assigned to 108 everyone his fate, or “share.” At the birth of man she spun the thread of his future life, pursued his footsteps, and directed the consequences of his actions, according to the decrees of Zeus. By some she was conceived as a fatal divinity, who directed human affairs in such a manner as to restore the right proportions or equilibrium, wherever it had been disturbed; who measured out happiness and unhappiness, and allotted losses and sufferings to him who was blest with too frequent gifts of Fortune, to the end he might be humbled into acknowledging the existence of bounds beyond which human happiness cannot proceed with safety.

To Homer she was not an absolute sovereign of both heaven and earth, to whom even the gods must bow; but merely apportioned the fate of men, as counseled by Deity. In the theology of Hesiod there were three: Clotho, the spinning fate; Lachesis, who assigned to man his fate; and 109 Atropo, who decreed a fate that could not be avoided. This conception answered to the Teutonic Norns, or Weird Sisters. What was to the earlier poets of Greece a person, Æschylus apprehended as a principle; a law for both gods and men; an over-ruling, ever-present, inevitable necessity, against which it is vain to contend, and from which it is hopeless to escape. “His characters are pre-determined parricides, murderers and adulterers.” For instance, the destiny of the pious Amphiaraus led him to that death his wisdom foresaw; fate impelled him to the society his judgment forbade. Good Eteocles, too, lies under the band of fate, but seeks not to avert the doom. “Stern, uncompromising, he will meet the man he must slay, by whom he must himself fall.” The inexorable destiny of Æschylus was to Sophocles and Plato an ordering of the divine will.

Two great schools of philosophy divided the educated opinion of classic Greece and 110 Rome. The tenets of both were fatalistic in tendency. What was to the Epicurean a “chance” appealed to the Stoic as “law.” Man, taught Epicurus, is a mere buffet of a blind fatality. The phenomenon of life, said Stoicism, is governed with iron sway by an imminent necessity of reason. “Man should be free from passion,” preached Zeno, “unmoved by joy or grief, and submit without complaint to the unavoidable power by which all things are governed.”

Buddhism is the doctrine taught by Gautama, the Hindoo sage, in the sixth century, B. C. ; now the belief of a greater part of central and eastern Asia and the Indian Islands. In this creed, fatality is a cardinal principle. Sir Edwin Arnold has designated it “The Light of Asia.” The great religion of Brahma, also, teaches that everything is subject to a divinely appointed necessity. It boasts a philosophy that was the admiration of Bruno, Schelling, Hegel, and Draper. Manes declared that the moral universe was 111 controlled by two supreme principles; one the author of all good, the other the author of all evil. The highest conception of Mohammed is an arbitrary and inexorable law. In the Koran we read: “No man can anticipate or postpone his end. Death will overtake us, even in lofty towers. From the beginning, God hath settled the place in which each man shall die.” The Persian poet sings: “The destinies ride their horses by night. No man can by flight escape his fate. Whether asleep in bed or in the storm of battle, the angel of death will find thee.” “I am convinced,” saith Ali, “that the affairs of men go by divine decree, and not by our administration.”

In the philosophy of Solomon, as recorded in Ecclesiastes, we read: “The thing that hath been, it is that which shall be; and that which is done is that which shall be done: and there is no new thing under the sun.... To everything there is a season, and a time to every purpose under 112 the heaven: a time to be born, and a time to die; a time to plant, and a time to pluck up that which is planted; a time to kill, and a time to heal; a time to break down, and a time to build up; a time to mourn, and a time to dance; a time to cast away stones, and a time to gather stones together; a time to embrace, and a time to refrain from embracing; a time to get, and a time to lose; a time to keep, and a time to cast away; a time to rend, and a time to sew; a time to keep silence, and a time to speak; a time to love, and a time to hate; a time of war, and a time of peace.”

With Christianity came the dogma of “predestination” and “election.” This was promulgated, on the very threshold, by Paul, a man of the sublimest genius; adorable, venerable and heroic. Thus he addressed the church at Rome: “And we know that all things work together for good to them that love God,—to them who are the called according to His purpose. For whom he 113 did foreknow, he also did predestinate to be conformed to the image of his Son, that he might be first born among many brethren. Moreover whom he did predestinate, them he also called: and whom he called, them he also justified: and whom he justified, them he also glorified. What shall we say to these things? If God be for us, who can be against us?”

This idea is necessarily involved in the theology of St. Augustine, who maintained that “grace is effectual from its nature, absolutely and morally, not relatively and gradually.” It remained for John Calvin to erect the assertions of Paul into a cognate and masterly system. He insisted upon the purpose of God from eternity, respecting all events.

Briefly, of the religion of the world, to-day, ninety per cent are predestinarian in theory or practice, consciously or unconsciously. Of Christendom, those who agree with Arminius are in a small minority, 114 relatively:—a minority whose creed involves not only the limitation of divine knowledge, but a paralysis of divine power and the moral chaos of a universe. That religion is necessarily puerile and unphilosophic which attempts to reconcile the omnipotence of God with the freedom of man. Either Nature is ordered for the best—so as to produce the highest good; or else, everything is purposeless and for the worst. In a word, either optimism or pessimism must wholly prevail: logically, a middle ground is impossible. We must choose between Leibnitz or Schopenhauer.

Literature and religion aside, the greatest intellects have promulgated a “philosophy of necessity.” Everything that exists, wrote Oersted in substance, depends upon the past, prepares the future, and is related to the whole. “Everything throughout creation is governed by law: but over most of the tracts that come within the active experience of mankind, the governing hand is so 115 secret and remote, that until very large numerical masses are brought under the eye at once, the controlling power is not detected.” Jonathan Edwards said: “Nothing comes to pass without a cause. What is self-existent must be from eternity, and must be unchangeable; but as to all things that begin to be, they are not self-existent, and therefore must have some foundation for their existence without themselves.” Spinoza urged that “In no mind is there an absolute or free volition; but it is determined to choose this or that by a cause, which likewise has been fixed by another, and this again by a third, and so on forever.” Emanuel Kant contended that “every action or phenomenon, so far as it produces an event, is itself an event or occurrence, which pre-supposes another state wherein the cause is to be met with; and thus everything that happens is but a continuation of the series, and no beginning which occurs of itself is possible; consequently, all the 116 actions of the natural causes, in the succession, are themselves again effects.” Our own Emerson asserted the omnipotence and omnipresence of law: “That the wilful and the fantastic, the low and the lofty, are encircled by a necessity.” Whatever limits us, we call fate. If we are brute and barbarous, the fate takes a brute and dreadful shape. If we rise to spiritual culture, the antagonism takes a spiritual form.... The limitations refine as the soul purifies, but the ring of necessity is always perched at the top.

None greater than these may be found in the noble realm of speculative thought. They are unequalled by few, if any. The whole field of modern science, also, is in accord with their deductions: Teaching that nature is an inevitable sequence, and that all phenomena, material and mental, are linked together by an inevitable connection. In the words of Herbert Spencer: “Various classes of facts unite to prove 117 that the law of metamorphosis which holds among the physical forces, holds equally between them and the mental forces. Those modes of the unknowable which we call motion, light, heat, chemical affinity, etc., are alike transferable into each other, and into those modes of the unknowable which we distinguish as sensation, emotion, and thought; these in their turns being directly or indirectly re-transferable into the original shapes.”

Would you dethrone man, I am asked? No; I surrender to the behests of philosophy as fortified by the deductions of science. Years ago it was argued by Comte that, in social order, the higher must subordinate itself to the lower. That the organic finds itself controlled and limited by the inorganic world, and man has to work out his destiny in submission to all the necessities, physical, chemical and vital, which are pre-supposed in his existence. “The higher,” he continued, “can overcome the lower only by 118 obedience; if it is to conquer, it must at least ‘stoop to conquer.’” And as was once stated by Doctor Conolly, “All the superiority of man, all those faculties which elevate and dignify him, this reasoning power, this moral sense, these capacities of happiness, these high aspiring hopes, are felt and enjoyed and manifested by means of the nervous system. Its injury weakens, its imperfections limit, its destruction ends them.”

But, it may be asked, is not this a denial of “free-will?” Yes, as popularly understood. A “free-will,” in the metaphysical sense, is impossible. The conception is unknown to the best modern psychology. The abstract will, of certain metaphysicians, is a phantasm. Individual volitions, only, come within our actual experience. They have been generalized, by mental philosophers, into a self-existent, self-sustaining, and self-procreating entity. However, an abstraction is not an essence. Such men but tell us what a “free will” 119 should be; that it exists has never been demonstrated. Again, the phenomenon “will” is now known to be transmitted from generation to generation. Heredity teaches that its energy and its weakness are connected with certain states of the organism. “We can no longer doubt the transmission takes place by means of the organs, and, in fact, that the ‘will’ is physiological.” Moreover, in a philosophical sense, the idea is “at war” with a uniform law of cause and effect. Chance events are inconceivable in a universe of causation. Freedom of the will, therefore, is a delusion. For ages men believed that the sun revolved around the earth, because it seemed to do so. A similar illusion is at the base of our ethical system, since we enjoy only the appearance of liberty. “Our apparent freedom consists in the absence of all physical restraints, and in our power to do as we please; but what we please to do depends upon our mental constitution and the circumstances 120 in which we are placed.” The idea was beautifully expressed by Emerson in his poem “Fate.”

“Deep in the man sits fast his fate,
To mold his fortune, mean or great:
Unknown to Cromwell as to me
Was Cromwell’s measure or degree;
Unknown to him as to his horse,
If he than his groom be better or worse,
He works, plots, fights in rude affairs,
With Squires, Lords, Kings, his craft compares,
Till late he learned, through doubt and fear,
Broad England harbored not his peer.
Obeying time, the last to own
The genius from its cloudy throne,
For the prevision is allied
Unto the thing so signified;
Or say, the foresight that awaits,
Is the same genius that creates .”

In human history, as in physical nature, therefore, every event is linked to its antecedent by an unavoidable connection, and such precedent is connected with an anterior effect; and thus the whole would form a necessary chain, in which, indeed, each man may play his part, but can by no means determine what the part shall be.

121 The moral actions of men, said Buckle, are the product of their antecedents. In other words, when an action is performed, it is performed in consequence of certain motives; those motives are the results of some antecedents; “therefore, if we were acquainted with the whole of the antecedents and with all the laws of their movements we could with certainty foretell the whole of their immediate results. This great social law is liable to disturbances which trouble its operation, without affecting its truth.”

Ergo, given any set of circumstances, and nothing could have happened, save that which did happen; and under exactly the same conditions, the conduct of men must ever issue in the same results. The past should be dismissed without regrets. Our position, at any time, should be judged as it really is, and not for what we vainly suppose it might have been; “for nothing is more certain than that we could not have 122 acted differently in any act of our lives, with the state of mind and circumstances then existing.”

Statistics, likewise, are daily making it evident that the same fixed calculable laws exist in the departments of life and mind as in physics. “In individual cases, or in a limited circle, apparent uncertainty may exist. Within a given number of cases, however, and a large field, invariable results may be looked for.”

In the 12th annual report of William Farr, Esq., to the Registrar General of England, we are told “it may be broadly stated that 27 in 1000 men of the population of the age of 20 and under 60, are suffering from one kind of disease or another; that several are of long duration, that others are recurrent, and that some are hereditary.” We are informed in a subsequent report of the Registrar himself, that it seems to be a “law” one person out of every 45, living at the commencement of any year, 123 will die within that year. (The entire system of insurance—life, fire, and marine—is erected on the principle contended for in this chapter. Not only do a certain relative number of men die in each class annually, but the law extends to the number of policies lapsed each year. There seems also to be a periodicity in the number of fires and marine disasters.)

According to Porter and Buckle, even “marriage is not determined by the temper and wishes of the individual, but by large general facts over which individuals can exercise no authority. It is now known that marriages bear a fixed and definite relation to the price of corn.” A century’s experience in England demonstrates that marriages are regulated by the average earnings of the great mass of people. Cheapness of provision and not love regulates the number of nuptials. Combe affirms the same striking coincidence in the ratio of births in Great Britain.

124 Another singular fact has been deduced from the official reports of England and France. “Even forgetfulness is under a constant law.” Buckle is an authority for the statement that “year after year, the same proportion of letter-writers forget to direct their letters, in some part; so that for each successive period we can actually foretell the number of persons whose memory will fail them in regard to this trifling occurrence.”

By the same witness we prove “the uniform reproduction of crime is more clearly marked, and more capable of being predicted than are the physical laws connected with the disease and destruction of our bodies.” Before this, Combe had observed a similar uniformity, under similar circumstances, of the recurrence of crimes. He perceived in human conduct the same striking indications of constancy in results, as in the prevalence of disease and the endurance of life. Combe said, in 1854, in writing 125 by way of comment on a certain report to the House of Commons: “During the five years, ending with the last year of an execution, there were committed for the crimes enumerated, 7276 persons, of whom 196 were executed. During the five years immediately following the last execution, there were committed for the same offense 7120. Does not this show that these crimes arose from causes in themselves permanent, and which punishment does not remove?” Rawson also remarked that the greatest variation which had taken place during three years, in the proportion of any class of criminals, at the same period of life, had not exceeded a half per cent.

And Dr. Brown states (Vol. 8 of the Assurance Magazine), that “in twenty years, the number of persons accused of various crimes in France, and registered under their respective ages, scarcely varies at any age, from year to year, comparing the proportional per cent under each age with the 126 totals.” M. Quatelet deduced from the statistical returns of government in the same country, that for 1826, 1827, 1828, 1829 and 1830, in each year, there was one person accused out of every 4463 inhabitants, and 61 condemned out of every 100 accused. “In everything which concerns crime,” observed this greatest of statisticians, “the same numbers re-occur with a constancy which cannot be mistaken, and that this is the case, even with those crimes which seem quite independent of human foresight, such, for instance, as murders, which are generally committed after quarrels arising from circumstances apparently casual. Nevertheless, we know from experience, that every year there not only take place the same number of murders, but even the instruments by which they are committed, are employed in the same proportion.” Murder, then, “occurs with as much regularity as the movements of the tides and the rotation of the seasons.”

127 “Self-murder,” Buckle observes, “seems to be not only capricious and uncontrollable, but also very obscure in regard to proof.” Yet, in different countries, for which we have returns, we find, year by year, the same proportion of persons putting an end to their own existence. In London, for example, about 240 persons make away with themselves every year; the annual suicides oscillating, from the pressure of temporary causes, between 266, the highest, and 213, the lowest. In 1846, which was the great year of excitement—caused by the railroad panic—the suicides in London were 266; in 1847 began a slight improvement, and they fell to 256; in 1848 they were 247; in 1849 they were 213; in 1850 they were 229.

In the “Journey through India,” Heber mentions the vain attempt of the English government to check the frequent suicides by drowning, committed at Benares; and August Comte has exposed the folly of 128 thinking that suicide can be diminished by the enactments of law-givers.

Of this field, Quatelet says, in conclusion: “The possibility of assigning, beforehand, the number of accused and condemned which should occur in a country, is calculated to lead to serious reflections, since it involves the fate of several thousands of human beings, who are impelled, as it were, by an irresistible necessity, to the bar of the tribunal, and towards the sentences of condemnation that there await them. These conclusions flow directly from the principle, already so often stated in this work, that effects are in proportion to their causes, and that the effects remain the same, if the causes which produced them do not vary.”

Another step is needed to complete our argument in this branch. Actions are the production of motives. Motives are the effects of determinate antecedents. Whence these antecedents? They are to be found 129 in the “Law of Heredity.” Reproduction is governed by law, and “like begets like.” To quote from Voltaire: “The physical, which is ‘father of the moral,’ transmits the same character from father to son for ages. The Appii were ever proud and inflexible; the Catos always austere. The whole line of the Guises were bold, rash, factious, full of the most insolent pride and most winning politeness. From Francis de Guise down to that one who put himself at the head of the people of Naples, they were all in look, courage and character above ordinary men. I have seen full length portraits of Francis, of Balafre and his son: they were all six feet high, and they all possess the same features—the same audacity on the brow, in the eyes, and in the attitude.” M. Taine sees in Lord Byron a true descendant of the Berserkers. To Ribot, the French of the 19th century are the Gauls described by Cæsar and Strabo. Amphere writes of the character of the 130 Greeks, that it has not changed; “he has now the same qualities, the same defects as of old.” The physiology and mentality of parents characterize their offspring. The human mind is not a blank at birth. Its capabilities and character are inherited. Every possibility of the soul is innate and constitutional from the moment of gestation. Such is the verdict of science substantiated by Ribot, Galton, and Fowler.

That the peculiar anatomy and physiognomy of races is persistent and hereditary, must be admitted. The truth is verified by every-day experience. We see it in the Englishman, the Frenchman, the Spaniard, and Scandinavian. The intellectual characteristics of a people are likewise transmitted from generation to generation. The Indian, for example, is ever wild, free, cunning and revengeful. Negroes, on the other hand, are generally timid, garrulous, urbane and polite. The Hebrews, again, are noteworthy for intellectual 131 calibre, the acquisitive faculty, and a clannish spirit.

In the family, likewise, likenesses and stature pass from generation to generation. So, also, of size. Fowler found this exemplified everywhere. Some of his illustrations were taken from the Websters, Franklins, and Folgers. Muscular strength is hereditary, as with the Douglas, Fessenden, and Garrish families. Physical deformities and excrescences obey this edict of nature; and it includes disease, insanity, gray hair, premature death, propensities, length of life and beauty. The truth is overwhelming that mental faculties and qualities descend from child to child. These sequences in mental phenomena operate through generations upon caution, self-esteem, firmness, pride, benevolence, and religious feeling. Talent and ability go by descent. Even genius, although akin to divine, is transmissible. “Each generation,” said Galton, “has enormous power over the natural gifts 132 of those that follow.... The results of an examination into the kindred of about 400 illustrious men of all periods of history were such, in my own opinion, as completely to establish the theory that genius was hereditary.”

Now for my application. Gambling, in some form, is a propensity of the general mind: an inclination now hereditary in the race. That such must be the case is clear from Ribot, Maudsley and Da Gama Machado. “The dead rule over the living,” writes Spencer. “Past generations exercise power over present generations, by transmitting their nature, bodily and mental.”

The origin and development of gambling were obvious to the eminent astronomer, Richard A. Proctor. “Beyond doubt,” he said, “the element of chance which enters into all lives, has had a most potent influence in moulding the characters of men. If we consider the multitudinous fancies and superstitions of men like sailors, farmers, 133 and hunters, whose lives depend more on chance than those of men in some other employments, and recognize this as the natural effect of the influence which chance has on their fortunes, we need not consider it strange if the influence of chance, in moulding the minds and characters of our ancestors during countless generations, should have produced a very marked effect on human nature. An immense number of those from whom I inherit descent must, in the old savage days, have depended almost wholly upon chance for the very means of subsistence. When, wild in wood, the savage ran, he ran on speculation. He might, or he might not, be lucky enough to earn his living on any day, by a successful chase, or by finding such fruits of the earth as would supply him with a satisfactory amount of food. He might have much depending on chances which he could not avoid risking, as the gambler of to-day has when he ‘sees red’ and stakes his whole 134 fortune on a throw of the dice or a turn of the cards. We cannot be doubtful about the effects of such chance influences even on the individual character. Repeated, generation after generation, they must have tended to fill men with a gambling spirit, only to be corrected by innumerable generations of steady labor; and, unfortunately, even in the steadiest work, the element of chance enters largely enough to render the corrective influence of such work on the character of the race much slower than it might otherwise be. Every man who has to work for his living at all, every man who has to depend in any way, on business for wealth, has to trust to chance, in many respects. So that all men, in some degree, more or less, have their characters modified by this peculiarity of their environment. The inherited tendency of each one of us towards gambling, in some one or other of its multitudinous forms, is undoubtedly strengthened in this way.”

135 First, we see, it cannot be said that gambling is immoral, sinful, or irreligious. Second, it is clear the propensity to gamble is as natural as the temperament or complexion. The law can no more destroy the natural inclination of the mind, than it can make “one hair white or black.” If an evil (which in the absolute sense I deny), it is not to be prevented by legislation. It is no more possible, by direct effort, to change the gaming proclivity in man than to stem the torrent, or check the eternal progress of the glacier. The growth of centuries, down it moves through the years in an irresistible march. Absurd seem all our demonstrations; how idle, the beating of the air. When one form passes away another immediately takes its place. Disappearing here, it appears there. Apparently suppressed in one place it breaks out with more vigor in another. Continue it will, and continue it must, whether practiced openly or in secret. If it is not the faro-bank or 136 lottery it is something worse. If not the gambling-rooms of a Morrissey, a Daly, a Pendleton or a Hankins, it will be the mammoth palaces (boards of trade and chambers of commerce, so-called), which now are a feature of every city in Christendom, and wherein millions upon millions are wagered annually upon the very bread and meat wherewith our life is sustained; wherein billions are lost and won, sometimes to the injury of every department of actual production. There are the open boards of trade, too, wherein the petty transactions aggregate many millions. I am told by those who have made it a study for years, that more than 80 per cent of the transactions on the exchange are fictitious: mere betting on the rise and fall of commodities in price. All authority in this matter is practically powerless. Inclinations will be satisfied, and until inclinations change, the demand will be supplied; this, moreover, in the face of laws however stringent, or police 137 supervision however effective. Such methods are not only ineffective, but absolutely injurious to society. No nation or government has succeeded in restricting, limiting, or curing the gambling spirit and practice. That this is true, I call upon every candid and fair-minded man of experience to bear witness. I appeal to lawyers, judges, statesmen, scientists, philosophers, and the police and municipal authorities throughout the United States and Europe to corroborate my statement. The sooner this is generally realized, the better for humanity. What I have to suggest, instead of the present policy, is reserved for consideration in another place. I may say here, however, that for the law to punish what it cannot thereby cure is absurd—absurd as is every attempt to accomplish the impossible. Systematic education is the only hope; incessant training the only remedy for appetites and propensities; either for their correction, restraint, or subversion. If it had been revealed to 138 man that gambling is a sin, even that would not vitiate our reasoning in this chapter. God, or absolute wisdom, should be able to reconcile the existence of an evil with His own Sovereignty. However, this chapter is not concerned with the realities of religion, or the true principles of philosophy. As human conceptions, they have been noted as in accord with the teachings of science; to show that the human intellect responds intuitively to what are subsequently known as the laws of nature.


139

Legislative Exorcism;
or,
The Belief in Word-Magic.

141

CHAPTER IV.
Legislative Exorcism; or, The Belief in Word-Magic.

For ages, mankind were believers in magic. One of the phases was Exorcism, or a pretended exercise of supernatural power, through certain words of magic import. “Healing words,” says Van Helmont, “were used against the devil and all diseases.” And it is asserted by the Zendavesta that “many cures are performed by words.” That the magic power of words was a belief of the Greeks and Romans, is evident from their literature. Thus it is said of Plotin, that while in Sicily he cured Porphyrius of a fever, “by wonder-working words.” We are told how Orpheus’ song 142 calmed the storm, and how Ulysses “stopped the bleeding of wounds by the use of certain words.” They also tell us, that with words, Cato cured sprains; Marcus Varrus removed tumors; and Servilius Novianno restored sight to the eyes. It is gravely stated by Pliny that Cato did not alone use the words, “motas, daries, dardaries, astaries,” but likewise a green branch, four or five feet long, which he split in two, and caused to be held over the injured limb. A similar power was ascribed to the philosopher, Pythagoras. And if “ye olden chronicle” is to be credited, the curses of Peter of Amiens and Bernard of Clairvaux, “produced fearful spasms and sufferings, whilst their blessings restored speech to the dumb and health to the sick.”

The belief in magic is not general in our age of the world. It has gradually retired before the march of reason and the light of scientific truth. That all nature, organic and inorganic, animate and inanimate, is subject to a universal law of cause and effect, is now 143 a truism to every educated person. Science has forever destroyed the curative influence of phrases. Reason sternly excludes verbal formulæ from the realm of physical causation. That any mere words may be used against disease or injury is now denied by enlightened opinion the world over. In medicine, therefore, Exorcism is a thing of the past.

One aspect of the superstition still remains, as an obstacle to the progress of humanity; the possibility of legislating morality into men. Law-givers still cling to the power of “exorcism” by statute. Their blind creed is: “beatification and education by law.” “To them, laws are the cows, whose teats mankind should suck. To them, men are as dough, which their wisdom would knead.” This adoration of the law and legislators was systematically inculcated by the 18th century publicists: Montesquieu, Robespierre, Rousseau, and St. Just. They seem to teach that “the law cannot come out of us, but must be poured into us.” But, as 144 Erlanger has said with truth, he who undertakes to give institutions to a people must feel within himself the capacity to change human nature, to metamorphose every man, to transmute the constitution of each individual, to strengthen them; in one word, “he must take from mankind their own powers, and impart to them a foreign power.”

Statesmen should recognize with Carpenter, that “society is the gigantic growth of centuries, moving on in a resistless and orderly march, with the precision and fatality of an astronomic orb.” The huge being marches on with elephantine tread. The liberal sits on its front and the conservative on its rear; but both are swept along, whether they will or not, and both are shaken off ere long, inevitably, into the dust. One reformer shouts “this way,” and another cries “that,” but down comes the great foot and crushes both, indifferently; the man who thought he was right, and the man who found he was 145 wrong; crushing, alike, him who would facilitate, and him who would impede its progress. At least, it should be kept in mind, “that laws are made by the people, and not the people by the laws.” Modern society is so burdened by an enormous and complex overgrowth of law, that the necessity for its existence is now a prevailing notion, to the end that men may be kept in order: that, without the oppressive institution, people would not follow a systematic life. On the other hand, all observation of civilized races discovers the directly opposite. The instinct of man is to regularity of life, and law is but a result or expression of this. “As well attribute the organization of a crab to the influence of its shell, as ascribe the orderly life of a nation to the action of its laws.” The law may have a purpose, but to believe it will preserve order is illusive. This it certainly does not effect, even with all its machinery of police, courts and prisons. Fichte said: “The object of all government 146 is to render government superfluous.” The same idea has been expressed by Whitman and Paine. Moreover, “if external authority, of any kind, has a final purpose, it must be to establish and consolidate an internal authority. When this process is complete, government, in the ordinary sense, is already rendered superfluous.”

The world has been slow (or loath) to learn the only proper functions of government. This must be clear to every reader of Bruce Smith, Lieber and Dick. In the governments of oriental antiquity, political authority was clothed with a super-eminent and absolute jurisdiction over the whole life of its subjects; “the manners of their subjects, their rank, their condition, mode of life, and daily occupations, were all fixed by the law.”

And, in the opinion of Grecian philosophers, the state was everything, the individual nothing. In their judgment, the government should not permit any individual to waste 147 his power and energy, nor should he be allowed to misdirect it. They insisted the law must first devise the model of a perfect citizen; and then, by a system of discipline, mould, or rather distort, into agreement therewith, the character of every citizen. The powers of state, therefore, should embrace individual life in its entirety; from infancy to mature age, “in all conditions and relations, whether domestic, religious, social, industrial or political.”

Such teachings had their illustration in the administration of Greek governments. In Sparta, for example, under the reign of Lycurgus, the citizen belonged to the state, rather than to the family. The individual Athenian did not have a right the Archons were “bound to respect.” Draco punished even laziness with death, and Solon prohibited costly sacrifices at funerals. In Greece, Lycurgus seems to have been the first legislator against luxury. He enacted, for example, that no Spartan should own a 148 house, or household article, which had been made with a finer implement than an axe or a saw; and that no cook should use any other spice than salt and vinegar. Our authorities are Ephorus and Diogenes Laertius. The sumptuary prohibitions of Solon, according to Plutarch, were aimed at the female passion for dress, as well as the pomp of funerals. He likewise placed surveillance over the luxury of banquets.

The Dorian races were disposed to austere and rigid habits of life. A Laconian could not lawfully attend a drinking entertainment. In Lacedæmonia, frugality and simplicity were the object of the pheiditia. Gold and silver were interdicted, and their legislation permitted the use of iron money alone. In Magna Græcia, the Pythagoreans encouraged the sumptuary policy. Zaleucus, the Locrian legislator, enacted that no woman should appear in public wearing gold ornaments, or embroidered apparel, unless her designs were unchaste.

149 Roman statesmen were not wiser, in their day, than those of Greece. From the time of the Kings, they sought by law to regulate luxurious tendencies. We find it in the law of the Twelve Tables: “Do not carve the wood which is to serve for a funeral pile. Have no weeping women to tear their cheeks; no gold, no coronets.” Certain foreign articles of luxury were prohibited about 189 B. C. An important part of the legislation of Sulla, Cæsar, Crassus, Antony, Augustus and Tiberius, related to the expenditures for food, funerals and games of chance. Says Plutarch: “The Romans thought the liberty ought not to be left to each private citizen to marry at will, to choose his manner of life, to make feasts; in short, to follow his desires and his tastes, without being subject to the judgment and supervision of anyone.” The Oppian Law forbade matrons to have more than a half-ounce of gold, to wear garments of diversified color, or to use carriages in Rome. 150 Following a revolt of the Women, in 195 B. C. , this law was abrogated. Inspired by Cato, the Censor, fourteen years later, the Orchian Law was promulgated. It limited the table expenses, as did the Fannian Law twenty years after. The Lex Orchia limited the number of guests to be present at a feast. The general cost of entertainment was fixed by the Lex Fannia. A limit of one hundred asses was established for some festivals, and thirty asses for others. Ordinary entertainments were restricted to ten asses. The Didian Law extended to all Italy.

In Greece, sumptuary laws were seldom or never regarded by the people, who always entered into a tacit and general conspiracy against their enforcement. Notwithstanding the Roman notatio censoria , luxury continued to increase with the growth of wealth. No law of senate or emperor could restrain the tendency. “From first to last,” writes the historian, “all were habitually transgressed.” 151 In the time of Tertullian they appear to be of the past.

Instances of like legislation disfigure the statute-books of every civilized country downward from the fifth century, A. D. All sumptuary laws, at Rome, were formally repealed by the later emperors; but the folly thereafter re-appeared when European society began to rally and segregate under Charlemagne. To illustrate, “in the latter middle ages, knights were allowed to wear gold, and esquires only silver; the former damask, the latter satin of taffeta; when the esquires used damask, velvet was reserved for the knights.” The first legislation of this character, in the modern world, was enacted by Frederick II., in Italy; James I., in Aragon; Philip IV., in France; Edward II. and Edward III., in England. Commencing in France with Charlemagne, it first became extensive and flourished under Philip IV. and Charles VI. From Edward III. until the Reformation, it was in great favor in 152 England. Great was the absurdity to which legislators were carried by this vain policy. In Scotland, for example, one parliament forbade ladies to attend church with the face muffled in a veil, and another fulminated against superfluous banqueting and the inordinate use of foreign spices; while a Danish law provided that no servant girl should wear her hair curled. The edicts of Philip IV. related to extravagance at table and in dress. An edict of Charles V. forbade the use of long-pointed shoes. Charles VI. allowed no one to exceed a soup and two dishes at dinner. Later French kings sought to restrict the use of gold, silver, silks, embroidery, and fine linen. From Blanqui we take a sample ordinance of the character under consideration. “The said Lord the King, being duly informed that the great superfluity of meat at weddings, feasts and banquets, brings about the high price of fowls and game, wills and decrees that the ordinance on this subject be renewed 153 and kept; and for the continuance of the same, that those who make such feasts, as well as the stewards who prepare and conduct them, and the cooks who serve them, be punished with the penalties hereunto affixed. That every sort of fowl and game brought to the markets shall be seen and visited by the poulterer-wardens, in the presence of the officers of the police and bourgeois clerks to the aforesaid, who shall be present at the said markets, and shall cause a report to be made to the police, by the said wardens. The public shall be likewise bound to live according to the ordinance of the King, without exceeding the limit, under penalty of such pecuniary fines as are herein set forth against the inn-keeper, so that neither by private understanding nor common consent shall the ordinance be violated.” During the same year, another ordinance provided “that no bourgeois woman shall have a chariot; no bourgeois man or woman shall wear green, or grey, or ermine, and 154 they shall dispose of those they have, by a year from Easter next. The dukes, counts and barons of 6000 livres, in land, or more, may have four robes a year, and no more, and the women as many. A knight who has 3000 livres, in land, may have three robes a year and no more; and one of these three robes shall be for summer. At the principal meals of the day no one shall have but two viands and a pork soup, and let him not deceive about it. It is ordained that no prelate or baron shall have a robe for body of more than 25 Tournish sous, a Paris ell.” In 1294 it was decreed “that every manner of people, who have not an income of 6000 Tournish livres, shall not use, and will not be able to use, any gold or silver plate for drinking, for eating, or for other use, and that no person, under penalty of fine and imprisonment, shall practice any fraud about it.”

In France, laws of this character disappeared near the end of the 16th century. 155 Under Louis XV. all such laws were practically a dead letter. “These ordinances are the history of but yesterday,” says an able and profound student of French legislation; “but ideas and sentiments have gone far in advance of facts. We have difficulty in comprehending the interference of government in the domestic affairs of families, and in contracts which concern only private individuals. Opinion has undergone an entire revolution. Sumptuary laws can no longer be proposed. We need not think the change is due to our wisdom, to our pretended superiority to the ancients; let us simply recognize that the essential principle of society has changed; the world moves on another basis.... In no century were these laws observed to any great extent. Enactments of this kind were never effectual in France. Since the Revolution, no sumptuary laws have been enacted, and yet the luxury of attire which formerly distinguished the nobility has disappeared. A duke dresses like 156 anybody else, and he would be ridiculed if he sought to distinguish himself by a manner of dress different from others.”

It has been observed by one of the great statesmen of England, that the broad principles of freedom had been early recognized in that country, and understood by even the citizens of minimum intelligence; for instance, freedom of locomotion, freedom in the disposition of property, freedom of opinion in politics and religion. But that other important features of the same principle were not so quickly and clearly understood. “I refer,” he continues, “to such matters as freedom of commercial intercourse and exchange, freedom of contract in the natural rise and fall of wages and in the condition of labor; freedom of individual taste and expenditure, in the more private concerns of life. In many cases, these were matters which affected the poor and rich alike, but principally the poor, who, in their meagre parliamentary representation, enjoyed 157 few opportunities for effectual protest. One can only account for the continuance of those which materially affected the better classes, who did enjoy representation, to the fact that, not being familiar with the fundamental economic laws, which are now so widely understood, they were not prompted to any practical resistance. It is highly probable, too, that for want of this knowledge, most people rested satisfied with the vague idea that, in some way or other, though not very clear, such restrictive legislation produced some good to somebody.” We pass over those legislative and executive interferences, which present “every possible contrivance for hampering the energies of commerce.” Purely economic questions are not germane to our discussion; such as the numerous and ingenious restraints upon foreign trade; the attempts to regulate the rate of wages and the price of food.

Richard II., Henry IV., and Edward IV. legislated against the liveried suits of the 158 nobility. This was also prohibited by Henry VII.; and yet, even under James I., says Hume, “we find ambassadors accompanied by a suite of 500 or 300 noblemen.” During the reign of Edward III. it was enacted that no man should be allowed more than two courses at dinner or supper, or more than two kinds of food in each course. Three courses were permitted on the festival days of the year. Foreign cloth was allowed to the royal family alone. Unless a man possessed at least £100 per annum he was forbidden furs, skins and silks. During the same reign, another act divided the people of England into classes, and prescribed the apparel of each. In the social scale it did not go higher than knights, and minutely regulated the clothing of women and children. It was repealed the following year. In 1363 it was enacted that servants should have only one meal a day of flesh or fish. The statute of 1444 attempted to regulate the price of clothing for each year: a bailiff, 159 50 s. ; principal servant, 40 s. ; ordinary servant, 33 s. 4 d. James I., of Scotland, forbade not only “sumptuous clothing,” but the use of pies and baked meats, to all under the rank of baron. The Scottish sumptuary law of 1612 was the last in Great Britain. The English laws were largely repealed during the reign of James I. A few remained on the statute book as late as 1856. Mr. Froude has exposed the folly of their existence.

It has been said of the English laws they “were at all times inspired by a desire to arrest an irresistible movement, resulting from the very force of things—from the logical development of human activity. They were, moreover, powerless, and always evaded by a sort of tacit and general conspiracy of all the citizens, without anyone being able to find fault with the principle, without anyone thinking of contesting the power of the legislator on this point.”

Roscher remarks: “In Ireland the government had endeavored for a long time to 160 preserve that country from the ravages of alcohol, by the imposition of the highest taxes, and the severest penalties for smuggling. Every workman in an illegal distillery was transported for seven years, and every town in which such a one was found was subject to a heavy fine. All in vain. Only numberless acts of violence were now added to beastly drunkenness.”

In another place, Roscher continues thus: “Where it has been attempted to suppress the consumption of popular delicacies, the impossibility of enforcing sumptuary laws has been most strikingly observed. Thus, in the 16th century, an effort was made as regards brandy; in the 17th, as regards tobacco; in the 18th, as regards coffee. The Hessian law of 1530 provided that only apothecaries should retail brandy. In 1624 Papal excommunication was fulminated against all who took snuff in church, and was repeated in 1690. According to a Turkish law of 1610, all smokers should have 161 their pipes broken against the nose. In 1634 a Russian law prohibited smoking under penalty of death. In Switzerland, even in the 17th century, no one could smoke except in secret. In its native place even coffee had a hard struggle. Prohibited in Turkey in 1633 under pain of death; it was still prohibited in Basel in 1769, and could be sold by apothecaries only as medicine. In Hanover the coffee trade was prohibited in 1780. When governments discovered the fruitlessness of these efforts, they gave up the prohibition of these luxuries, and instead substituted taxes on them, thus aiming to combine a moral and a fiscal end. Even Cato took this course. His office of censor, which united the highest moral superintendence with the highest financial guidance, must of itself have led him in this direction.”

Strange it is how slowly men learn by experience. We know of the many oppressions in England “for opinion’s sake.” History tells us that the puritan fathers 162 sought “freedom of conscience” in the wilds of America. Yet, scarcely were the “pilgrims” of New England wonted to a strange and inhospitable land, than what they required for themselves was denied to others. In their fanaticism, the “soul liberty” of Roger Williams was violated in every conceivable way. Personal freedom was violated to an extent that is now the detestation of right-thinking persons. Execrable for their tyrannical spirit, are some of the records of Massachusetts Bay, Plymouth, New Haven Colony and Connecticut. The following extracts are taken from the records of the General Court of the Colony of Massachusetts Bay:

“1635: Whereas, complaints hath bene made to this Courte that dyvers persons, within this jurisdiction, doe usually absent themselves from Church meetings upon the Lord’s Day, power is therefore given to any two assistants to heare and sensure, either by fine or imprisonment, all misdemeanors 163 of that kind, committed by any inhabitant within this jurisdiction, provided they exceede not the fine of 15 shillings for any one offense.”

“1669: Any person or persons that shalle be found smoking tobacco on the Lord’s Day, going to or coming from the meetings, within two miles of the meeting house, shall pay 12 pence for every such default to the colonies’ use.”

“1692: All and every justices of the peace, constables and tything men are required to restrain all persons from swimming in the water; unnecessary and unreasonable walking in the streets or fields in the toun of Boston, or other places; in the evening preceding the Lord’s Day, or any other part of the said day or the evening following.”

“1634: The court, taking into consideration the greate, superfluous and unnecessary expenses occassioned by some newe and immodest fashions, as also the ordinary wearing of golde, silver, silke, laces, girdles, 164 hat-bands, etc., hath, therefore, ordered that noe person, either man or woman, shall hereafter make or buy any apparell, either woolen, silke or lynen, with any lace on it, silver, golde, silke or thread, under the penalty of the forfeiture of such clothes.”

“1782: Be it enacted that each person, being able of body and mind, not otherwise necessarily prevented, who shall, for the space of one month together, absent himself or herself from the public worship of God, on the Lord’s Day, shall forfeit and pay the sum of ten shillings.”

In old Connecticut we find legislation similar in character. In 1647: “Forasmuch, as it is observed that many abuses are crept in and committed by the frequent taking of tobacco, it is ordered by the authority of this Court, that no person under the age of 20 years, nor any other that hath not accustomed himself to the use thereof, shall take any tobacco until he hath brought a certificate under the hands of some who are approved 165 for knowledge and skill in physic, that it is useful to him and that he hath received a license from the Court for the same.”

“1643: Whoever shall prophane the Lord’s Day, or any part of it, by unlawful sport, recreation or otherwise, whether wilfully or in careless neglect, shall be duly punished by fine, imprisonment, or corporally, according to the nature and measure of the sin and offense.”

Here are some of the celebrated New Haven “Blue Laws:”

“Whoever wears clothes trimmed with golde, silver or bone lace, above two shillings by the yard, shall be presented to the Grand Jurors, and the selectmen shall tax the offender at £300 estate.”

“No one shall read Common Prayer, keep Xmas or Saint’s Days, make minced pies, dance, play cards, or play on any instrument of music, except the drum, trumpet and jew’s-harp.”

166 “No one shall run on the Sabbath Day, or walk in the Garden or elsewhere, except reverently to and from meeting.”

“No one shall travel, cook victuals, make beds, sweep house, cut hair or shave, on the Sabbath Day.”

“No woman shall kiss her child on the Sabbath or fasting day.”

“If any man shall kiss his wife, or any wife her husband, on the Lord’s Day, the party in fault shall be punished at the discretion of the Court of Magistrates.”

“Every man and woman duly, twice a day, upon the first tolling of the bell, repair into the church to heare divine service upon pain of losing his or her day’s allowance, for the first omission; for the second to be whipped, and for the third to be condemned to the galleys for six months.”

“If any man, after legall conviction, shall have or worship any other god but the Lord God, hee shall bee put to death.”

“If any person turns Quaker, he shall 167 be banished and not suffered to return, upon the pains of death.”

“No priest shall abide in this dominion, he shall be banished and suffer death on his return.”

“No man shall hold any office who is not sound in the faith.”

“No food or lodging shall be afforded to a Quaker, Adamite, or other heretic.”

“Every man shall have his hair cut round according to a cap.”

Such are a few of the laws that disgrace the beginning of our national life. Repealed they never were, save by the scorn of time, or the revolt of the human heart, as it struggled into a wider and brighter existence. They were only effective as the expression of a spirit then prevalent. Forward marched the soul, and behind is left the hideous husk. Here and there, on the statute-books of certain states, vestiges may remain of Sabbatarian legislation, but they are a dead letter, to enforce which is seldom or never attempted.

168 Roscher observes, “That the puritanical laws, which some of the states have passed prohibiting all sales of spirituous liquors, except for ecclesiastical, medical or chemical purposes, have been found impossible of enforcement.” Said Dr. Dio Lewis on this subject: “A very striking illustration of the weakness of law, when it comes in contact with the instinct of liberty, is the result of prohibition in Maine. I have taken pains to learn the facts in that state. I traveled it throughout and conversed with a large number of its leading citizens, almost exclusively temperance men, and became satisfied (notwithstanding the prohibitory law), that intemperance is the great overwhelming curse of the Pine Tree State.” The Doctor then found fully 300 grog shops in Bangor. He says of Portland, also, the number of arrests for drunkenness in 1874 was 2011. He is authority for the statement that, in 1873, the state prison inspectors of Maine reported the enormous number of 169 17,808 arrests for drunkenness during that year.

Hon. James McGinnis, of the St. Louis bar, several years ago, gave the prohibitory legislation of the whole country (and its practical workings) an exhaustive consideration in all aspects. The results of his study, published to the world, revealed the same condition of affairs in Maine, New Hampshire, Vermont, Massachusetts, Rhode Island, Connecticut, New York, Delaware, Maryland, Ohio, Indiana, Nebraska, Iowa, and Kansas. On every hand, past and present, he “beheld the impracticability of prohibition.” “I now appeal,” he says, “to the fair-minded reader to give his thoughtful attention to the facts and figures which I have truly and fairly presented, to show that neither crime, pauperism, intemperance, nor any of the ills which are popularly supposed to grow out of intemperance, have been at all lessened by prohibition.”

The political economists are practically 170 unanimous in their reprobation of these laws. Adam Smith vigorously protests against their impertinence and presumption. Of sumptuary laws it has been said their enforcement is exceedingly difficult, as it is always harder to superintend consumption than production. “The latter is conducted in definite localities. The former is carried on in the secrecy of a thousand homes. Besides, such laws have very often the effect to make forbidden fruit all the sweeter.” Spite of the penalties attached to their violation, and of redoubled measures of control, government after government have been compelled to admit their failure in this direction. Laws of this nature always involve an abridgement of individual “liberty,” and of the natural right of every man to do what he “will” with his own. They involve the assumption, also, that a government, with the exercise of paternal authority can judge better than the citizen what will best subserve his or her welfare, in the use of what they have. “But such 171 action belongs more properly to the spiritual than to the temporal power. In ancient life, where there was a confusion of the two powers in the state system, sumptuary legislation was more natural than in the modern world, where those powers have been generally, though imperfectly, separated.”

“I have learned to doubt,” wrote Dr. Dio Lewis, “whether law is very potent in the cure of moral evil. Force is a good agency in breaking rocks and subduing wild beasts; but in curing immorality, in which we strive to regulate the action and reaction of the faculties and passions of the human soul, force is about as well adapted to our purpose as a sledge-hammer to regulating a watch. Some people seem to have the impression that society is restrained from evil by law; that our wives and daughters are virtuous because there is a law against prostitution; that our exemplary citizens refrain from profanity and excess in gaming and drinking because they are forbidden by 172 law; that somehow society is kept in order by law.

“It is not denied that Massachusetts has to-day upon her statute-books other laws involving the same violation of personal liberty as prohibition; but every law interfering with personal habits and propensities has no practical vitality.

“For example, prostitution is an enormous evil; and we have a severe statute against it; but, as a matter of fact, if a house of prostitution be conducted in a quiet, unobtrusive way, the authorities cannot break it up. If any prohibitionist can devise a method by which the authorities can break up such a house, it would be easy to sell his discovery to property holders of New York City for a hundred million of dollars.

“Scattered throughout this city (Boston) there are unnumbered rooms over stores, and other places of business, and in private houses, occupied by persons who are living in the relation of husband and wife without 173 legal marriage. There are not two punishments for every hundred thousand violations of the statutes against such intimacies.

“Gambling is very common in our city. There is a great number of rooms, or suites of rooms, devoted to this practice. In club houses and many hotels, gambling may be found every night, and often lasting all night. Not a fiftieth part of the gambling done in this city takes place in gambling rooms. Why does it never occur to anybody to attempt to enforce the law against gambling in our clubs and other private houses; should they attempt it they would signally fail.”

Although this was said of New England, it is representative of the United States and the civilized world. A like picture might be drawn of every city in our land and throughout Europe. Every candid and intelligent magistrate, or police official, in the country will admit that the law never has, and never can, prevent gaming, intemperance or prostitution. This has been publicly acknowledged 174 by the most eminent men of affairs in Europe. That it is impossible to suppress or exterminate the “social evil” has been demonstrated by Acton, Tait, Parent and Du Chatelet. The latter avows that “licensed houses are the most judicious and the most consistent with good morals.” The police establishments of the continent, finding it impossible to prevent the existence of houses of ill-fame, realized the necessity, not of authorizing, but of licensing them. The vice is now subject to police supervision in Paris, Toulon, Lyons, Strasburg, Brest, Hamburg, Berlin, Vienna, Naples, Brussels, Rheims, Bordeaux, Marseilles, Copenhagen, Madrid, Malta, Lisbon, Amsterdam and St. Petersburg. A like policy obtains in Bombay, Hong Kong, Japan, New South Wales and Cape Colony.

On the contrary, England wages war against prostitution. Is it with success? No; in this respect her cities are the worst in Europe. In that country 42,000 illegitimate 175 children were born in 1851. It was estimated that within the five years preceding, 212,000 females had strayed from the paths of virtue, and thus taken the first step in prostitution. In 1832, London had a population of 1,000,000, and her known prostitutes numbered 10,000. Within her limits were then 3,300 brothels. At that time, in Liverpool, there were 5,000 fallen women. Of houses of ill-fame Dublin had 355; Edinburgh, 219; Glasgow, 204; Liverpool, 770; Manchester, 308; Birmingham, 797; Hull, 175; Leeds, 179; Norwich, 194. In England, in 1865, there were 500,000 prostitutes. It has been computed that the unfortunates number about 86,000 in the London of to-day. It is not surprising, then, that the constabulary of Great Britain are in despair of their power for good over this evil. “Sooner or later (they realize) the principle of individual liberty must triumph, and prostitution must become, under the shadow of general principles, as unrestricted as any other commerce, moral or immoral.”

176 In New York City, also, the law has always attempted to repress the “social evil,” but without avail. This has been openly recognized by those in authority. In 1875, 1876, and 1877 licensed prostitution was recommended by a committee of the State Legislature, the Grand Jury of the City and County of New York, and the Commissioner of Public Charities and Correction. The committee assumed “that houses of prostitution must exist;” and its members, therefore, took it upon themselves “to earnestly recommend to the Legislature the regulating, or permitting,” or, as they phrased it, “if the word be not deemed offensive, the licensing of prostitution.” In June, 1876, the Grand Jury of the Court of General Sessions of the same county and state, made an official presentment concerning prostitution, in which they say “that however abhorrent to the views of some, any legislation may be, which appears to legalize so great an evil, still the fact must 177 not be lost sight of that it is an evil impossible to suppress, yet comparatively easy to regulate and circumscribe.” They conclude with a memorial to the Legislature, “to adopt as early as practicable some system of laws calculated to confine houses of prostitution, in the large cities of this state, within certain specified limits, and to subject them at all times to a careful and vigilant supervision of the Boards of Health and Police.”

Punitory laws never have, and never will cure the evils to which society is liable. “Life is sweet,” some one has said, and yet even the death penalty does not prevent murder. If the menace of death is not a deterrent, what can be said for lesser penalties like fines and imprisonment. That capital punishment is not a preventive of crime was (upon investigation) the conviction of Bentham, Beccaria, George Clinton, Lord Brougham, Judge J. W. Edmunds, William H. Seward, Wendell Phillips, Douglas Jerrold, Cassius M. Clay, Dr. Lushington, 178 Edward Livingston, Theodore Parker, Vice-President Dallas, DeWitt Clinton, Victor Hugo, Mittermaier, John Howard, Sir Samuel Romilly, Earl Russell, Lord Houghton, Lord Osborne, John Bright, Lord Hobart, Lord Kelly, Frederick Robertson, Prof. Fawcett, Charles Dickens, John Stuart Mill, Canning, Thomas Jefferson, and hundreds of other able, thoughtful and conscientious men. Their position was not only grounded on observation, but fortified by the experience of Tuscany, Spain, Italy, Switzerland, Bavaria, Belgium, San Marino, Denmark, Norway, Sweden, Michigan, Wisconsin, Minnesota, Maine, Vermont, and Rhode Island. “There is no passion in the mind of man,” said Lord Bacon, “so weak, but it mates and masters the fear of death; and therefore death is no such terrible enemy when a man hath so many attendants about him that can win the combat of him. Revenge triumphs over death; love slights it; honor aspireth to it; grief fleeth to it; fear occupieth it.” 179 And if “the fear of the great future,” writes Bovee, “when painted with the horrors such as only a Milton or a Pollok could depict, produces no more marked effect on human action; it is hardly reasonable to suppose that the menace of death by human law, will be very effective in the repression of crime.”

The truth is clear to Rev. Octavius B. Frothingham. He declares that neither crime nor vice can be prevented, remedied, or expelled by force of law. “Nature will have her way, if not by one channel, then by another. She will plunge underground, and come up in unexpected spots. Cunning comes to her assistance. She makes alliance with subterfuge and deceit. She is sly, swift, ubiquitous. Disappearing in New York, she turns up in Philadelphia. Expelled from the cities, she takes refuge in the towns; banished from the towns, she finds coverts in the cities; hiding in the dens and slums, creeping into the lanes, mingling with the 180 crowd of harmless things, sheltering herself behind law. She is a Proteus, able to take on every possible shape of innocence. Refuse her brandy, she will take opium, morphine, ether, tobacco, strong coffee, in quantities equivalent to the stimulant desired. You fancy the community becoming temperate in one respect, and find it becoming intemperate in another. Opium eaters multiply as dram-drinkers decrease. The propensity is alive still, and perhaps provoked to activity by the efforts made to suppress it. The natural appetite being reinforced by anger, spite, the spirit of resistance to persecution, which grows dogged and stubborn, fortifying the sense of injustice by the pride of self-will.

“As if impatient at the slowness of the converting process, weary of the task of planting vice out, of choking the weeds of instinct with the flowers of grace, the church undertook, with violent hand, to pull up the weeds by main force. Instead of abolishing the 181 hydra by a beautiful law of evolution, which should create a series of nobler growths; it undertook to cut off the poisonous heads, one by one. It took boys and girls, at the tenderest age, out of the world, confined them in religious houses, refused them the joy of the flesh, and the joy of the eyes, and the pride of life, barred the gates of every terrestrial garden, mortified their desires, kept them occupied with prayers and contemplations, and so tried to starve nature to death.

“Christianity, was as consistent, tried to repress the disposition to unbelief, in its opinion the most fruitful source of vice. The disposition to unbelief was regarded as the deadliest symptom of the natural, unconverted heart. To counteract it by an opposite disposition to belief was tedious and difficult, and the method of repression was resorted to. The civic power was enlisted in the work of exterminating pernicious error. Tribunals were created, laws were passed, 182 judges and executioners were appointed, penalties were devised, heretical schools were broken up, heretical books were burned, heretical teachers were banished, silenced, incarcerated, consigned to the flames. Whole provinces were devastated, towns were destroyed, populations turned adrift to perish; the entire field of unorthodox thought was ploughed over and sown with salt. And what was the result of the method, carried out on this vast scale, with full ecclesiastical and civil powers—the sacred and the secular authorities combining, the sympathy of the Christian world aiding, no public opinion opposing, the resources of wealth conspiring with the resources of fanaticism, to make the policy of suppression effective? The issue is familiar to all who care to know the truth, from the reports of historians, who have made it their business to ascertain and tell the facts. They certainly do not bear out the conclusion that the method of suppression is wise, or even practical. On the 183 contrary, they suggest the opinion that it is impractical as it is unwise. The failure of the method was so disastrous that it quite defeated the ends.

“If one thing is demonstrated by human history, it is this:—the attempt to suppress human nature, under any form, so it be nature that is suppressed, is futile. The old proverbs, which say, ‘Drive nature out at the door, and she comes in at the window;’ ‘You cannot expel nature with a fork;’ hold out a truth that is for all time.... Deeply rooted propensities, habits which have become a second nature, cannot be thus dealt with. No Hercules’ club will avail to kill the vital principle that grows venomous heads faster than they can be bruised. The effort to suppress nature by violent measures, is always followed, always produces a reaction, that is exactly proportioned in strength to the effort, and fairly balances it. Healthy progress is slow, gradual, measured, according to the sure conditions 184 of cause and effect. It consists of a long line of close sequences, knit together, not mechanically, like a chain, but organically, like a muscle or a nerve. Every inch of growth implies a preceding inch of growth; there is no such thing as jump or leap from point to point. You do not make the elastic band longer by stretching it; you but loosen the cohesion of its parts; the strain being relaxed, the band resumes its first condition; the strain being continued, the band looses its elasticity and breaks. There is no more power than there is.”

M. Guizot, statesman and historian, thought it a gross delusion to believe in the sovereign power of political machinery. Every day discloses a failure, every day there reappears the belief that it needs but an act of some legislative body and a corps of officials to effect any purpose. The faith of mankind is nowhere better seen. Disappointment has been preached from the first: “Put not thy trust in legislation.” Yet 185 the trust in legislation seems scarcely diminished. Is it not time to reject the law as a social panacea? We should now realize that measures are usually quite different in effect from what has been expected. It would be difficult to estimate the number of legislative disappointments in English and American history; “or the amount of harm which has been inflicted on society by abortive attempts at statesmanship.” History demonstrates the incapacity of law-givers. Says Mr. Jensen, “From the statute of Merton (20 Henry III.) to the end of 1872, there had been passed 18,110 public acts, of which he estimated that four-fifths had been partially or wholly repealed.” And Herbert Spencer estimated a few years ago that “in the last three sessions of the English parliament, there have been totally repealed 650 acts, belonging to the present reign alone.”

Buckle said, in this connection, every great reform has consisted “not in doing 186 something new, but in undoing something old. The most valuable additions made to legislation have been enactments destructive of preceding legislation, and the best laws which have been passed have been those by which some former laws were repealed.... We owe no thanks to law-givers as a class; for, since the most valuable improvements in legislation are those which subvert preceding legislation, it is clear that the balance of good cannot be on their side. It is clear that the progress of civilization cannot be due to those who, on the most important subjects, have done so much harm that their successors are considered benefactors, simply because they reverse their policy, and thus restored affairs to the state in which they would have remained, if politicians had allowed them to run on in the course which the wants of society required.”

In the name of “liberty and equality,” a brave battle has been fought for individuality. 187 Unjust and unwise interference by the state has been ably resisted. It is demanded that private judgment be released from the embrace of authority. The truth is, one man has no natural right to make laws for another. True, he may repel another, when his own rights are infringed, but he has no right to govern him. The individual is sovereign merely over himself, and not over his fellow-man.

The greatest minds now insist an individual will more freely act, not only for the furtherance of personal interests, but also for collective interests, without being constrained thereto by an external power. Whenever room is to be made, they say, for the advance of society, public authority must retire within its narrowest jurisdiction; yielding, because of its impracticability, all control over concerns purely personal. “Who remembers having done anything, or having refrained from doing anything, on account of the statutes? If we could realize how 188 little civil law contributes to the good conduct and well-being of society, our interest in legislators would be greatly lessened. Of the millions upon millions of acts of kindness and justice which go to make up civilized life, I take it that nine in ten would not be performed at all, if they were required by law.

John Stuart Mill has clearly defined the limit of individual “sovereignty”—as it is termed—and where the authority of society should begin. “Each will receive its proper share, if each has that which more particularly concerns it. To individuality should belong the part of life in which it is chiefly the individual that is interested; to society, the part which chiefly interests society.

“The acts of an individual may be hurtful to others, or wanting in due consideration for their welfare, without going the length of violating their constituted rights. The offender may then be justly punished by opinion, though not by law. As soon as any 189 part of a person’s conduct affects prejudicially the interests of others, society has jurisdiction over it, and the question whether the general welfare will or will not be promoted by interfering with it, becomes an open one. But there is no room for entertaining any such question, when a person’s conduct affects the interest of no person besides himself, or need not affect them unless they like, all the persons concerned being of full age, and with the ordinary amount of understanding. In all such cases there should be perfect freedom, legal and social, to do the action and stand the consequences.”

Everybody agrees with this proposition, in the abstract. At this period of time, nobody would dispute “personal liberty,” as a “glittering generality.” People are too smart for that. It would be impolite and unfashionable. They would agree with you, perhaps, that “personal liberty” is the source of all progress, the lever of all conquests, the inspiration 190 of all achievements. “The great, vital, pivotal fact of human life; all progress and all happiness begin and end in personal freedom.” O yes, they will readily agree with the rhetoric involved. “The prize, the precious jewel of the ages, is personal liberty. It has no equivalents. Untold wealth, a mine of diamonds, a palace, are baubles by the side of personal liberty. We recognize the supreme importance of this principle. We are willing that all men should be free—if they will only do what is best for them. We rejoice in the utmost liberty of opinion and action—if people will only do and say what is right.”

Thus is “freedom” trespassed upon, under pretence that is for the good of the man or men whose rights are violated. Such was probably the pretext for every tyrannical invasion of popular rights known to history. Thus was it quaintly put by Dio Lewis: “The Inquisition believed in the perfect liberty of all men to be Catholics, but if 191 they caught a man with other notions about salvation, they put a thumb-screw on him. Our Puritan fathers believed in personal freedom as no other men ever did. They left their homes, crossed a stormy ocean, and braved a thousand dangers, that they might be free to think and say what they pleased. And they were perfectly willing that all who came along might think and say what they pleased, unless, as sometimes unfortunately happened, the other men said and thought things which conflicted with the things which the fathers thought and said. They sometimes came across a Quaker, whose views did not seem quite the thing, and they hung him. Our New England fathers believed in ‘religious liberty.’ Indeed, ‘religious liberty’ was their constant boast; but if a man did not believe in hell, they would not let him testify in court.... But our fathers were always very kind about it; they said he was at liberty, perfect liberty, at any time to believe in hell, and then he might swear a blue streak.”

192 What is really meant by this definition of “personal liberty” is the absolute right of every individual that every other individual shall act, in every respect, exactly as he ought; “that whosoever fails thereof, in the smallest particular, violates my social right and entitles me to demand of the legislature the removal of the grievance.” “This doctrine,” continued Mill, “ascribes to all mankind a vested interest in each other’s moral, intellectual, and physical perfection, to be defined by each claimant, according to his own standard.”

Of this class of men Dr. Lewis well said: “They consider themselves born to control other men. They are ever inquiring, ‘What ought this man to do?’ and if that man refuses to do it, ‘How can we compel him?’ They proceed thus: ‘Resolved, That the righteous should govern the world. Resolved, That we are the righteous.’”

In what language can I fitly designate a principle of action so impertinent and 193 presumptious? Who can deny the moral “liberty” of his fellow creature, as an abstract proposition? Is not the moral equality, or independence of man one of his essential rights? Neither one, nor any number of persons, is warranted in saying to another of mature years, what the latter shall, or shall not do with his life for his own benefit. “He is most deeply interested in his own well-being; the interest which another person can have in it is trifling, compared with that which he himself has.” It is time for society to distinguish, sharply, between the province of morality and that of legislation. With the same end in view, perhaps, yet they should differ widely in extent. Admit that morals and the law have the same center, they have not the same circumference. There may be a moral guide to the conduct of an individual, through all the details of life, through all the relationships of society; but legislation cannot be this, and if it could, it ought not to exercise a continued 194 and direct interference with the conduct of men. There are many acts useful to the community which the legislator ought never to command; so are there many hurtful acts, which he ought not to forbid. There is certainly a broad distinction between moral and legal rights. For instance, “a man has no moral right to hate his wife, but he has a perfect legal right to hate her. A man has no moral right to foreclose a mortgage on a sick widow’s home, and turn her and her children out in the snow, but he has a perfect legal right to do it. A man has no moral right to make a glutton of himself, destroy his usefulness, and thus throw his wife and children on the town, but he has a perfect legal right to do it.” A man has no moral right to drink rum, but he has a perfect legal right to do so. What actions, then, may be legally punished as offenses? “What a question,” I hear some one exclaim; “are not all men agreed upon it? Do you ask us to prove an acknowledged truth.” 195 I answer in words of the great Jeremy Bentham: “Be it so. But on what is founded that agreement? Demand of each his reasons. You will find a strange diversity of interest and principles. You will find it not only among the people, but among philosophers.... The agreement which you see is founded only on prejudices; and these prejudices vary, according to the times and places, according to opinions and customs.... People have always said that such an action is an offense. Such is the guide of the multitude, and even of the legislator. But if usage has made innocent actions crimes; if it makes venial offenses appear heavy, and heavy offences light; if it has varied everywhere, it is clear that we must subject it to some rule.”

Vices are not rightly punishable by law. They are amenable to education only. Should A. assist B. to indulge in a vice, and A. uses no fraud or coercion, and B. is compos mentis , A. is not guilty of a crime, in the proper 196 sense. Suppose A. were a cook, who compounds for B. rich and delicious dishes, and of which B. partakes to such an extent that he sickens and dies, A. is not guilty of a crime. Neither is B.’s indulgence in the strong food or strong drink a crime punishable by law, only a vice amenable to discretion and judgment.

Correctly considered, then, a crime is an act which one man, with “malice prepense,” commits upon the person or property of another, without that other’s consent. Crime may be subject to law. A vice, on the other hand, is any act or passion in which a person may indulge himself: malice, hypocrisy, pride, envy, hatred, avarice, ambition, profanity, falsehood, indolence, cowardice, drunkenness, gluttony, tyranny, fanaticism, extravagance, etc., etc. Unless this distinction be recognized by the law, there can be no such thing as individual right, liberty or property, “no such thing as the right of one man to the control of his own person and property, and the corresponding 197 and co-equal right of another man to the control of his own person and property.”

An eminent and respected physician once said to an enlightened audience: “Not a person before me, but has suffered from vices; indeed, that is what we mean by the imperfection of human nature. When we depart from perfection it is a vice. Everybody is guilty of vices. The people before me, forty years old, should not be so old at fifty or sixty. Their teeth are decayed, and they have imperfect digestion. They do not enjoy the full and happy play of all their powers and faculties, and the greater part of this waste comes from vices. There are certain secret vices which cannot be publicly named, which are doing more to break down our vital force, make us prematurely old, and fetter our souls, than all the crimes committed in the country, and the legislature can do nothing to cure them.

“Without doubt, gluttony is the most destructive of all our vices. It obtains 198 among all classes, all ages, and both sexes. Eminent medical men, in England and America, declare that strong food can count ten victims, where strong drink counts one.

“Tobacco is doing more injury to the minds and bodies of our nation than all the murder, theft, burglary, and arson, and yet the legislature can do nothing to cure the tobacco curse.”

Dr. Lewis wisely continues: “It is not often possible to say of those acts that are called vices, that they are really vices except in degree. That is, it is difficult to say of any actions, or courses of action, that are called vices, that they really would have been vices, if they had stopped short of a certain point. The question of vice or virtue, therefore, in all such cases, is a question of quantity and degree, and not of the intrinsic character of any single act, by itself. This fact adds to the difficulty, not to say the impossibility, of any one’s—except each individual for himself—drawing 199 any accurate line, or anything like an accurate line, between virtue and vice; that is, of telling where virtue ends and vice begins. And this is another reason why this whole question of virtue and vice should be left for each person to settle for himself. Vices are usually pleasurable, at least for the time being, and often do not disclose themselves as vices, by their effects, until they have been practiced for many years, or perhaps for a life-time. To many, perhaps most, of those who practice them, they do not disclose themselves as vices, at all during life. Virtues, on the other hand, often appear so harsh and rugged, they require the sacrifice of so much present happiness, at least, and the results which alone prove them to be virtues, are so often distant and obscure, in fact so absolutely invisible to the minds of many, especially of the young, that, from the very nature of things, there can be no universal or even general knowledge that 200 they are virtues. In truth, the studies of profound philosophers have been expended—if not wholly in vain, certainly with very small results—in efforts to draw the lines between virtues and vices.

“If then, it be so difficult, so nearly impossible, in most cases, to determine what is and what is not, vice; and especially if it be so difficult in nearly all cases to determine where virtue ends and where vice begins; and if these questions, which no one can really and truly determine for anybody but himself, are not to be left open and free for experiment by all, each person is deprived of the highest of all his rights as a human being; to wit: his right to inquire, investigate, reason, try experiments, judge and ascertain for himself, what is, to him, virtue, and what is, to him, vice; in other words, what, on the whole, conduces to his happiness, and what, on the whole, tends to his unhappiness. If this great right is not to be left free and open to all, then each man’s 201 whole right as a reasoning human being, to liberty and the pursuit of happiness is denied him.” “It is now obvious, for the reasons already given, that government would be utterly impracticable, if it were to take cognizance of vices and punish them as crimes. Every human being has his, or her, vices. Nearly all men have a great many. And they are of all kinds: physiological, mental, emotional, religious, social, commercial, industrial, economical, etc. If government is to take cognizance of any of these vices, and punish them as crimes, then, to be consistent, it must take cognizance of all and punish all impartially. The consequences would be, that everybody would be in prison for his, or her, vices. There would be no one left to lock the doors upon those within. In fact, courts enough could not be found to try the offenders, nor prisons enough built to hold them. All human industry in the acquisition of knowledge, and even in acquiring the means of subsistence, 202 would be arrested; we should be all under constant trial or imprisonment for our vices. But even if it were possible to imprison all the vicious, our knowledge of human nature tells us that, as a general rule, they would be far more vicious in prison than they ever have been out of it. A government that shall punish all vices impartially, is so obviously an impossibility, that nobody was ever found, or ever will be found, foolish enough to propose it. The most that any one proposes is, that government shall punish some one, or, at most a few, of what he esteems the grossest of them.”

“But this discrimination is an utterly absurd, illogical and tyrannical one. What right has any body of men to say, ‘The vices of other men we will punish, but our own vices nobody shall punish? We will restrain other men from seeking their own happiness, according to their own notions of it; but nobody shall restrain us from seeking our own happiness, according to our 203 notion of it. We will restrain other men from acquiring any experimental knowledge of what is conducive or necessary to their own happiness; but nobody shall restrain us from acquiring an experimental knowledge of what is conducive or necessary to our own happiness.’ Nobody but knaves and blockheads ever think of any such absurd assumptions as these. And yet, evidently, it is only upon such assumptions that anybody can claim the right to punish the vices of others, and at the same time claim exemption from punishment for his own. The greatest of all crimes are the wars that are carried on by governments to plunder, destroy and enslave mankind.”

It has been asserted that gambling is a vice. I deny that such is the case. The proposition cannot be established, as an absolute principle. If a man chooses to risk his money, on a game of cards, he has a perfect right to do so, in the abstract, 204 and no man, or any body of men, has a right to forbid him. “It is his money, and he has a right to do what he chooses with it. He has a legal right to put it in a gun and shoot it away, or burn it up, or risk it on a game of chance, or make any other disposition of it, and no man, or body of men, has a right to interfere.” For my purpose, as a question of law, the real question is whether a man may dispose of his own as he chooses? If so, then he has a right to wager it on a game of cards, or at dice; and it is absurd to treat as criminal another man who may join in with him in gaming, as an antagonist. In other words, “If John has at any time or in any place, the right to wager his money on a game of chance, then it is absurd to treat as criminal the helping John to do what he has a right to do. If one participant in a transaction is guilty of crime, so is the other. But if one participant is guiltless, then the other is guiltless.”

205 The keepers of gambling resorts are denounced, as though they were responsible for the gambling propensity in mankind. Now, resorts for gambling do not cause the passion. It is a tendency to which all men are prone, more or less. “The essential fact is the existence of this passion. There can never be any great difficulty in obtaining the means for its gratification.” If not one way, then in another. If at all, attack the principle, in whatever guise or by whomsoever practiced. If some methods are denounced, then should all methods be denounced. If those who furnish certain “means to the end” are to be punished as criminals, then should all persons who furnish any “means to the end.” But to punish any such person is erroneous and very short sighted; for the primary cause of the trouble, if such it be, is the desire for gaming. It is impossible to prevent its gratification. As wisely attempt “to make one’s hair white or black” by virtue 206 of “the statute in such cases made and provided.”

Suppose the law efficacious, with what consistency does our jurisprudence make gambling a crime? In general, at common law, all games are lawful, unless fraud has been practiced. Each of the parties must have a right to the money or thing played for. He must give his free and full consent, and the play must be conducted fairly. The mutual promises of the parties to the wager are held a sufficient consideration. A large number of such actions have been sustained by the courts of England and the United States.

For example, it was held that a wager of fifty guineas by one of the litigants that an appeal from a decree of Chancery would be reversed by the House of Lords, was not, of itself, void, there being no charge of fraud. So, wagers as to the time when a railroad would be completed; or, as to the name of a person whom one 207 of the parties had seen; or, as to the age of one of the parties; or, upon the price of an article of commerce; or, as to who would die first, of two persons not privy to the wager; or, as to whether A. would hit a target; or, upon foot or horse races; were held valid. Indeed, the tendency of the courts to discourage wagers of every nature is relatively of recent date. In many of the United States, the doctrine has been abrogated by statute. Texas, Delaware, California, and some other states still adhere to the English rule.

Some of the judgments in England were rendered by the greatest of judicial minds: Lord Mansfield, Lord Holt, Lord Hardwicke and Lord Kenyon. In the language of Lord Holt: “When considered in itself, there is nothing in a wager, contrary to natural equity, and the contract will be considered as a reciprocal gift, which the parties make of the thing played for, under certain conditions.” Lord Mansfield laid it down, 208 that wagers are actionable: “and that the restraints imposed on certain species, by acts of parliament, are exceptions to the general rule, and prove it.” And Lord Kenyon declared in Good vs. Elliott: “Being bound by former decisions, not having the power to alter the law, not finding any one case against the legality of wagers in general, and finding cases without number, wherein wagers have been held to be good, and that the payment of them may be enforced, I adjudge the wager in the present case good at common law.” It was a wager that A. had purchased a certain wagon of B.

The source of our jurisprudence is the common law of England. Gambling was not a crime under this system, and here it would enforce the contract of wager. I therefore denounce as incongruous and irrational a statute which seeks to punish the wagerer as a criminal.

Crime, at common law is something 209 essential, so, in its very nature; grounded in the Mosaic decalogue and the reason of things: murder, mayhem, adultery, robbery, theft, arson. The wager is akin to none of these, nor does it come within their spirit. The common law branded as a criminal him only whom God had thus branded. The wagerer was not of the number.

In a word, is gambling malum in se ? In answer, the common conviction of men has never so regarded it. The common law has ever recognized a boundary line which separates the mala in se from the mala prohibita . In law, a thing is malum in se when absolutely evil in itself; “not, indeed, in a philosophical sense,” says the eminent lawyer, James C. Carter, “but absolutely, according to the universal conviction, in the political society which so views it; and mala prohibita are those things, otherwise innocent or indifferent, which the legislative power, having control over the subject, may 210 declare to be offenses.” Although not malum in se , gambling may be malum prohibitum . If the latter, then it becomes merely a question of public policy whether or not the state shall license gambling, subject to such conditions as the police power might impose. At any rate, to the extent that government is a moral entity, it cannot rightfully punish gambling as being bad in itself.


211

“The King is Dead—Long Live the King.”

213

CHAPTER V.
“The King is Dead—Long Live the King.”

Expressive was the coronation ceremony in the ancient Dukedom of Carinthia. The ducal candidate, in a peasant’s garb, and with head proudly erect, walked towards the marble throne of his ancestors. But upon it was already seated a peasant, attended by the black bull and the lean horse—those sad and severe symbols of his class. Then was commenced between them this rude dialogue:

Peasant:—“Who so proudly dares enter here? Is he a just judge? Has he the good of the country at heart?”

Duke:—“He is and he will.”

214 Peasant:—“I demand by what right he will force me to quit this place?”

Duke:—“He will buy it of you for sixty pennies, and the horse and the bull shall be yours.”

Nowhere, in the past, was the sovereignty of the people more haughtily declared, than in this formality of the old Carinthians. “It bears the seal of remote antiquity—of an Homeric or Biblical simplicity.” That the people were the only true source of power, was admitted even in the archaic periods of history. Of olden time, there were many forms of popular government. Aristotle made a study of their institutions. Greece had her democracies and Italy a great republic. In Asia, then, as now, the assertion of political power was the sole foundation for its maintenance.

With the development of Christianity, in Europe, was inculcated the theoretic idea. Kings were anointed and they ruled by “divine right.” In the language of Mr. 215 Tiedeman: “The king, who in theory obtained his authority from God, acknowledged no natural rights in the individual. Individual activity, for its room, depended upon the monarch’s will.” In time, however, came the Reformation and political revolutions in England, France, the Netherlands, Spain and Italy. To-day, the “divine right” of kings is generally repudiated. It has been displaced by the ancient principle that all power is derived from the people. “The people were once subjects of the king. The government is now subject to the people.” “The king is dead,” but his functions yet live in “the state,” or the people.

While many ancient statesmen and publicists recognized the proper origin of power in government, their opinions as to its nature and extent were neither clear nor sound. Wherever lodged, in their judgment, power was limitless and irresponsible. Whether exercised by king or emperor, by an aristocracy or the people, it was absolute. 216 Politically, in other words, the individual was annihilated by the state. Government did not permit the existence of any personal right that it “was bound to respect.” This is also true of later times, in continental Europe. True, the “divine right” of kings was repudiated, but not the doctrine of absolutism. “ Vox Populi, Vox Dei ,” became the general answer to all complaints of the individual against the encroachments of popular government upon his rights and liberty. In the name of the people, atrocious crimes were perpetrated by revolutionary governments.

In its proper sense, individual liberty is a development of the Anglo-Saxon institutions. This doctrine is fundamental to the English Constitution. The principle is cardinal and vital in the American system of government. Individual rights are protected by constitutional restrictions upon power, federal and state. In the United States, every individual is a king. This accords 217 with the so-called laissez-faire doctrine, of modern development in England and the United States, which confines the sphere of government within the narrowest limits, and denies to it the power to do more than provide for public order and personal security, by the prevention and punishment of crimes and trespasses. Under the influence of this wholesome principle, with us and in Great Britain, for one hundred years, the encroachments of government upon the rights and liberties of the individual have been comparatively few.

In other words, it has been generally admitted by the wisest and broadest statesmanship, that private rights and personal liberty do not exist by the permission of municipal law. They are natural and founded upon the law of reason; that, therefore, governmental restraint should “only go to the limit necessary to a uniform and reasonable conservation of private rights.” Municipal law protects and develops, rather 218 than creates private rights and personal liberty.

In the United States this “limit” has been generally fixed at the power to enforce the common and civil law maxim, “ sic utere tuo, ut alieum non lædas .” The “police power,” it is called, and extends, in its broadest sense, to the preservation of peace and good order to the protection of property rights, “and of the lives, limbs, health and comfort of all persons.” Any law which goes beyond this, in the United States, at least, and undertakes to abolish rights, the exercise of which do not infringe upon the rights of others; or limits the exercise of rights beyond what is necessary for the public welfare and general security, is not properly within the police power.

The police power, then, is properly concerned only with crimes and trespasses. It cannot rightfully invade the realm of ethics, as such. Crime is theoretically a direct injury to the public, and trespass, a direct injury 219 to the individual. A vice, on the contrary, is the inordinate gratification of one’s desires and passions. The primary damage is to one’s self. In contemplating the nature of a vice, we are not conscious of a trespass on the rights of others. Vice does not fall within the police power. Expressed in the language of Mr. Tiedeman, “the object of police power, is the prevention of crime—the protection of rights against the assaults of others. The police power of the government cannot properly be brought into operation for the purpose of exacting obedience to the rules of morality, and banishing vice and sin from the world. The moral laws can exact obedience only in foro conscientiæ . The municipal law has only to do with trespasses. It cannot be called into play in order to save one from the evil consequences of his own vices, for the violation of a right, by the action of another, must exist or be threatened, in order to justify the interference of law.”

220 The people of this country are generally convinced of this truth. So widespread is the conviction that, where a law “does not have for its object the prevention or punishment of a trespass upon rights, it is impossible to obtain for it an enthusiastic and unanimous support.” Besides, it is true of every community, when “public opinion is aroused to an activity that will enforce a law for the prevention of vice, the moral force alone will be ample to suppress it.” But it is sometimes urged that an otherwise ineffectual statute may serve to direct public opinion in the right direction. To this I reply that one unerring truth is taught by the history of legislation: “It is the utter futility, in a corrective sense, of a law whose enactment is not the unavoidable resultant of the forces then in play in organized society. Nothing so weakens the reverence for law, and diminishes its effectiveness, as still-born statutes.”

Certain matters are generally recognized 221 to be within the police power of the state. For instance, the control of infectious and contagious diseases, of the insane, of habitual drunkards, spendthrifts, vagrants and mendicants. And finally, by forced construction, it has been extended to the liquor traffic. The law, it is said, may prohibit the sale of liquor to minors, lunatics, persons intoxicated, confirmed inebriates, and other persons with certain weaknesses of character. Courts maintain that while the liquor traffic is subject to the police power, yet it may not be entirely forbidden as necessarily injurious to the public in a legal sense. To quote the Supreme Court of Indiana, in Beabe vs. State: “Where injury does result (from the use of beverages) it is usually caused by the shortcomings of the purchaser, without any participation in the wrong of the seller. No business can be prohibited altogether, unless its prosecution is necessarily and essentially injurious. It is the abuse and not 222 the use of beverages that is hurtful. The use of beverages is not necessarily destructive to the community.... Fire-arms and gunpowder are not manufactured to shoot innocent persons, but are often so misapplied. Axes and hatchets are not made and sold to break heads with, but are often used for that purpose. Yet who has ever contended the manufacture and sale of these articles should be prohibited as a nuisance. We repeat, the manufacture and sale of liquors are not necessarily hurtful, and therefore may not be entirely prohibited.”

So much for the “police power,” generally considered. But what of its relation to gambling, if any? If the practice is neither a crime nor a trespass, then it is not rightfully subject to public regulation. I have demonstrated to the candid judgment that, of itself, gambling is not essentially wrong. I insist that, at least, in the absence of fraud and chicane, it is neither sinful, nor criminal. 223 To gamble with another is not to assault his person or property by main force. To wager or bet upon the laws of chance, deceit aside, is not to kill, maim, rob, or cheat your fellow man; the players freely participate in the hope of gain or for amusement. Then wherein is the action either felonious or tortious? Why should the police power interfere? That it cannot properly do so, under our institutions, is conceded by Mr. Tiedeman. He is an able and accomplished lawyer, and recognized by the profession as an authority on the subject. But it may be said, the effects are injurious, and for that reason the state may forbid the practice. That gambling is “necessarily and essentially” injurious to society, I deny. As a pastime, it is innocent, as a principle of action it permeates the business world. If an amusement, it may be abused to the detriment of certain individuals, but the abuse of a thing, innocent in itself, does not make that thing a crime. When an occupation, 224 it is but natural that the laws of chance should operate unevenly: to the advantage of some and to the disadvantage of others. Uniformity of success in affairs is impossible.

Throughout the business world, in every department of human activity, the losers but bear a fixed proportion to the winners. Some must fail that others may succeed. Such is the law of existence, as society is constituted to-day. We are not now concerned with ideals. The realities suffice for my purpose. Chance is at present the great motive power of the world. It sustains hope, and stimulates endeavor. Through its operation men are enriched and nations aggrandized. That some meet with disaster and encounter misfortune does not prove that appeals to chance are criminal in their nature, nor that such appeals are “necessarily and essentially” injurious to the state. Consistently, therefore, gambling cannot be forbidden because in its pursuit some persons are fool-hardy and others unfortunate.

225 I may be asked, “What do you suggest?” I would license gambling, and place it under such restrictions as would tend to lessen its abuse. I am willing, for practical purposes, to concede this much to the police power. If this policy may be claimed for the liquor traffic, why not for gambling also? Is gambling more injurious than intemperance? No, the victims of alcohol outnumber the unfortunate gamblers a thousand to one. The habitual use of intoxicants is necessarily and uniformly injurious to the individual. This is not true of gambling, as a pastime. The player may win. Some of the players must win. Whatever can be said against the prohibition of the liquor traffic, applies with greater force to gambling. If there are reasons why the sale of intoxicants may be licensed, by the state and municipal authorities, such reasons serve but to demand a like privilege for gambling. Briefly, the rule laid down by the Indiana Supreme Court as to the 226 liquor traffic, in Beabe vs. State, is clearly applicable to games of chance as a business. This is obvious from the whole tenor of my discussion. If the state is not willing to take this step, then leave the matter to “local option.” Leave it to the municipal authorities, whether gambling is to be permitted or not, in a given locality. Let it be a question of policy and toleration, if you will. Regulations may be imposed, as with the saloon. Recognize the existence of gambling as a fixed fact, but interpose a surveillance for the prevention of fraud. As with the saloon, also, provide for the protection of those weaklings who are ever wards of the law: “minors, drunkards, lunatics and spendthrifts.” This policy now obtains generally on the continent of Europe, and to a certain extent in several of the United States: notably, Arkansas, Texas and California.

“What! would you have gambling public?” Yes, rather than private; and that is the 227 alternative presented to the wise. The experience of California, in this matter, is that of every state in the Union, and all may profit by her example. In the words of Judge Murray of that state: “The Legislature, finding a thirst for play universally prevalent throughout the state, and despairing of suppressing it entirely, attempted to control it in certain bounds, by imposing restrictions and burdens on this kind of business. The license operated as a permission, and removed, or did away with the misdemeanor as it existed.” The issue for practical men is: Shall gambling be in sight and subject to control, or shall it be out of sight and beyond control. The “situs” of public gambling is known to the authorities, and thus may its conduct be supervised and regulated: its every operation may be hourly inspected by the police, to the exclusion of those whom the law may with propriety protect from their own acts, and the prevention of cheating by dishonorable methods 228 and devices. If gambling is public, in brief, its abuses can be reduced to a minimum. When repressed at known points, gambling is not thereby discontinued. It is thus distributed over a wider field, there, secretly to thrive in its worst features. Then it is that fraud and theft are triumphant: that “brace” gamblers “wax fat” and their conscienceless harpies pray in secret upon the unwary and the inexperienced. Public gambling is generally fair and honest. Secret gambling is too often but another name for a robbery that cannot be prevented by either police or magistrates. Again, the number of employees are few, comparatively, in the public gambling club, and it is without other allurements than naked chance may offer. Not so the private institution, the patrons of which may freely partake of most seductive viands and expensive liquors; rents are also higher, and more employees are required. The private club is costly in the extreme: 229 an extravagant scale is necessary to its very existence. This is a severe test to the scruples of a proprietor. In some way he must meet expenses and insure a livelihood. For an honest gambler the maintenance of a private club is seldom possible.

“But public gambling would be a temptation to the poor man. You admit that poor men should not gamble?” I answer, who is the “poor” man? When you have found him, who is his keeper? Are you the custodian of his judgment and inclinations? I am of opinion he would repudiate your guardianship with indignation. “Consistency thou art,” indeed, “a jewel.” The rich and well-to-do may gamble, perhaps, but not the man of small resources. I ask, who has the right, for that reason, to say the latter nay? Not you, rich gambler in stocks and farm products; nor you, sir, who nightly gamble in the parlor of a comfortable home, 230 or at the private club you assist in maintaining for that purpose. By what authority were you constituted the keeper of a less fortunate neighbor? All this aside, however, the suppression of public gambling will not deter any man from the pursuit, whether “rich” or “poor.” A thousand avenues are opened to him, despite the law and the authorities. In this matter, society must trust to the education of individual character and the gradual amelioration of mankind. Besides, if gambling were subject to regulation, as other pursuits, our laws could the better protect whomsoever it might desire.

Transcriber’s Notes

Punctuation, hyphenation, and spelling were made consistent when a predominant preference was found in the original book; otherwise they were not changed.

Simple typographical errors were corrected.

Unbalanced quotation marks were remedied when the change was obvious or the quotation was found in other sources. The others remain unbalanced.

The illustration on the Title page is a decorative floral; the other illustrations are decorative headpieces.

Page 109 : “the band of fate” was printed that way.

Page 187 : Opening quotation mark has no matching closing mark.